exercises 7,8,9,10 on pages 38, 39,40
HOW TO THINK
LOGICALLY
Second Edition
GARY SEAY
Medgar Evers College, City University of New York
SUSANA NUCCETELLI
St. Cloud State University
PEARSON
Boston Columbus Indianapolis New York San Francisco Upper Saddle River
Amsterdam Cape Town Dubai London Madrid Milan Munich Paris Montreal Toronto
Delhi Mexico City Sao Paulo Sydney Hong Kong Seoul Singapore Taipei Tokyo
Editorial Director: Craig Campanella
Editor in Chief: Dickson Musslewhite
Executive Editor: Ashley Dodge
Editorial Project Manager: Kate Fernandes
Director of Marketing: Brandy Dawson
Senior Marketing Manager: Laura Lee Manley
Project Manager: Shelly Kupperman
Production Manager: Susan Hannahs
Senior Art Director: Jayne Conte
Cover Designer: Suzanne Behnke
Cover Art: Thinkstock
Full-Service Project Management: George Jacob,
lntegra Software Services, Ltd.
Composition: Integra Software Services, Ltd
Printer/Binder: RR Donnelley
Cover Printer: RR Donnelley
Text Font: 9.75/13, NexusMix
Credits and acknowledgments borrowed from other sources and reproduced, with permission, in this
textbook appear on the appropriate page within the text.
Copyright© 2012, 2008 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of
America. This publication is protected by Copyright, and permission should be obtained from the
publisher prior to any prohibited reproduction, storage in a retrieval system, or transmission in
any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or likewise. To obtain
permission(s) to use material from this work, please submit a written request to Pearson Education, Inc.,
Permissions Department, One Lake Street, Upper Saddle River, New Jersey 07458 or you may fax your
request to 201-236-3290.
Many of the designations by manufacturers and seller to distinguish their products are claimed
as trademarks. Where those designations appear in this book, and the publisher was aware of
a trademark claim, the designations have been printed in initial caps or all caps.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Seay, Gary.
How to think logically / Gary Seay, Susana Nuccetelli.-2nd ed.
p. cm.
Includes index.
ISBN-13: 978-0-205-15498-2
ISBN-10: 0-205-15498-0
1. Logic-Textbooks. I. Nuccetelli, Susana. II. Title.
BC108.S34 2012
160-dc22
2011014099
14 16
PEARSON ISBN 10: 0-205-15498-0
ISBN 13: 978-0-205-15498-2
Preface xi
About the Authors xiv
Part I The Building Blocks of Reasoning 1
brief contents .-.�?
CHAPTER 1 What Is Logical Thinking? And Why Should We Care? 3
CHAPTER 2 Thinking Logically and Speaking One’s Mind 24
CHAPTER 3 The Virtues of Belief 49
Part II Reason and Argument 71
CHAPTER 4 Tips for Argument Analysis 73
CHAPTER 5 Evaluating Deductive Arguments 94
CHAPTER 6 Analyzing Inductive Arguments 122
Part Ill Informal Fallacies 145
CHAPTER 7 Some Ways an Argument Can Fail 147
CHAPTER 8 Avoiding Ungrounded Assumptions 166
CHAPTER 9 From Unclear Language to Unclear Reasoning 187
CHAPTER 10 Avoiding Irrelevant Premises 209
Part IV More on Deductive Reasoning 227
CHAPTER 11 Compound Propositions 229
CHAPTER 12 Checking the Validity of Propositional Arguments 261
V
(/)
1-
z
w
1-
z
0
0
IJ..
w
a:
co
1111
CHAPTER 13 Categorical Propositions and Immediate Inferences 293
CHAPTER 14 Categorical Syllogisms 330
Solutions to Selected Exercises 365
Glossary /Index 386
Index 396
detailed contents
Preface xi
About the Authors xiv
PART I The Building Blocks of Reasoning 1
CHAPTER 1 What Is Logical Thinking? And Why Should We Care? 3
1.1 The Study of Reasoning 4 Inference or Argument 4 • 1.2 Logic and Reasoning 5
Dimensions of the Subject 5 Formal Logic 5 Informal Logic 6 Exercises 7 •
1.3 What Arguments Are 8 Argument Analysis 9 • 1.4 Reconstructing Arguments 10
Identifying Premises and Conclusion 10 Premise and Conclusion Indicators 11
Arguments with No Premise or Conclusion Indicators 13 Exercises 14
1.5 Arguments and Non-arguments 16 Explanations 16 Conditionals 17
Fictional Discourse 18 Exercises 19 Writing Project 21 Chapter Summary 21
• Key Words 23
CHAPTER 2 Thinking Logically and Speaking One’s Mind 24
2.1 Rational Acceptability 25 Logical Connectedness 25 Evidential Support 26 Truth and
Evidence 27 2.2 Beyond Rational Acceptability 28 Linguistic Merit 28 Rhetorical
Power 28 Rhetoric vs. Logical Thinking 29 Exercises 29 2.3 From Mind to
Language 32 Propositions 32 Uses of Language 33 Types of Sentence 35
2.4 Indirect Use and Figurative Language 36 Indirect Use 37 Figurative
Meaning 37 Exercises 38 • 2.5 Definition: An Antidote to Unclear
Language 42 Reconstructing Definitions 42 Reportive Definitions 43 Testing Reportive
Definitions 43 Ostensive and Contextual Definitions 45 Exercises 45 ■ Writing
Project 47 Chapter Summary 47 Key Words 48
CHAPTER 3 The Virtues of Belief 49
3.1 Belief, Disbelief, and Non belief 50 Exercises 52 • 3.2 Beliefs’ Virtues and
Vices 53 3.3 Accuracy and Truth 54 Accuracy and Inaccuracy 54 Truth and
Falsity 54 • 3.4 Reasonableness 56 Two Kinds of Reasonableness 56
3.5 Consistency 58 Defining ‘Consistency’ and ‘Inconsistency’ 58 Logically Possible
Propositions 59 Logically Impossible Propositions 59 Consistency and Possible
Worlds 60 Consistency in Logical Thinking 61 ■ 3.6 Conservatism and
Revisability 61 Conservatism without Dogmatism 61 Revisability without Extreme
Relativism 62 3.7 Rationality vs. Irrationality 63 Exercises 65 Writing
Project 69 • Chapter Summary 69 Key Words 70
vii
(j)
f
z
LJ.J
f
z
0
0
0
LJ.J
_j
LJ.J
0
PART 11 Reason and Argument 71
CHAPTER 4 Tips for Argument Analysis 73
4.1 A Principled Way of Reconstructing Arguments 74 Faithfulness 74 Charity 74
When Faithfulness and Charity Conflict 74 4.2 Missing Premises 76 • 4.3 Extended
Arguments 77 Exercises 78 4.4 Types of Reason 81 Deductive vs. Inductive
Reasons 81 Exercises 83 4.5 Norm and Argument 85 What Is a Normative
Argument? 85 Missing Normative Premises 87 Exercises 88 Writing
Project 92 Chapter Summary 93 Key Words 93
CHAPTER 5 Evaluating Deductive Arguments 94
5.1 Validity 95 Valid Arguments and Argument Form 97 ‘Validity’ as a Technical
Word 98 Exercises 99 Propositional Argument Forms 102 Categorical Argument
Forms 104 The Cash Value ofValidity 107 Exercises 108 ■ 5.2 Soundness 114
The Cash Value of Soundness 116 5.3 Cogency 116 The Cash Value of Cogency 117
Exercises 118 • Writing Project 119 • Chapter Summary 120 • Key Words 121
CHAPTER 6 Analyzing Inductive Arguments 122
6.1 Reconstructing Inductive Arguments 123 • 6.2 Some Types of Inductive
Argument 125 Enumerative Induction 125 Statistical Syllogism 128 Causal Argument 130
Analogy 133 Exercises 135 • 6.3 Evaluating Inductive Arguments 137 Inductive
Reliability 137 Inductive Strength 138 Exercises 140 ■ Writing Project 143
Chapter Summary 143 Key Words 144
PART Ill Informal Fallacies 145
CHAPTER 7 Some Ways an Argument Can Fail 147
7,1 What Is a Fallacy? 148 • 7.2 Classification of Informal Fallacies 149
7.3 When Inductive Arguments Go Wrong 150 Hasty Generalization 150
Weak Analogy 152 False Cause 153 Appeal to Ignorance 156 Appeal to Unqualified
Authority 158 Exercises 160 Writing Project 164 • Chapter Summary 164
Key Words 165
CHAPTER 8 Avoiding Ungrounded Assumptions 166
8.1 Fallacies of Presumption 167 • 8.2 Begging the Question 167 Circular
Reasoning 169 Benign Circularity 170 The Burden of Proof 172 • 8.3 Begging the
Question Against 173 Exercises 174 8.4 Complex Question 178
8.5 False Alternatives 179 • 8.6 Accident 181 Exercises 182 • Writing
Project 185 • Chapter Summary 185 • Key Words 186
CHAPTER 9 From Unclear Language to Unclear Reasoning 187
9.1 Unclear Language and Argument Failure 188 • 9.2 Semantic Unclarity 189
9.3 Vagueness 191 The Heap Paradox 192 The Slippery-Slope Fallacy 194
9.4 Ambiguity 195 Equivocation 196 Amphiboly 197 ■ 9.5 Confused Predication 199
Composition 200 Division 201 Exercises 203 ■ Writing Project 207
Chapter Summary 207 ■ Key Words 208
CHAPTER 10 Avoiding Irrelevant Premises 209
10.1 Fallacies of Relevance 210 10.2 Appeal to Pity 210 10.3 Appeal to
Force 211 ■ 10.4 Appeal to Emotion 213 The Bandwagon Appeal 214 Appeal to
Vanity 214 10.5 Ad Hominem 215 The Abusive Ad Hominem 216 Tu Quoque 216
Nonfallacious Ad Hominem 217 10.6 Beside the Point 218 10.7 Straw Man 219
10.8 Is the Appeal to Emotion Always Fallacious? 221 Exercises 222 ■ Writing
Project 226 ■ Chapter Summary 226 ■ Key Words 226
PART IV More on Deductive Reasoning 227
CHAPTER 11 Compound Propositions 229
11.1 Argument as a Relation between Propositions 230 11.2 Simple and
Compound Propositions 231 Negation 232 Conjunction 234 Disjunction 236 Material
Conditional 237 Material Biconditional 240 Exercises 241 ■ 11.3 Propositional Formulas
for Compound Propositions 244 Punctuation Signs 244 Well-Formed
Formulas 244 Symbolizing Compound Propositions 245 Exercises 247 11.4 Defining
Connectives with Truth Tables 251 ■ 11.5 Truth Tables for Compound
Propositions 254 11.6 Logically Necessary and Logically Contingent
Propositions 256 ■ Contingencies 256 Contradictions 256 Tautologies 256 Exercises 257
Writing Project 259 Chapter Summary 259 Key Words 260
CHAPTER 12 Checking the Validity of Propositional Arguments 261
12.1 Checking Validity with Truth Tables 262 Exercises 266 12.2 Some Standard
Valid Argument Forms 268 Modus Ponens 268 Modus Tollens 269
Contraposition 269 Hypothetical Syllogism 270 Disjunctive Syllogism 271 More Complex
Instances ofValid Forms 271 Exercises 273 12.3 Some Standard Invalid Argument
Forms 276 Affirming the Consequent 278 Denying the Antecedent 279 Affirming a
Disjunct 280 Exercises 281 ■ 12.4 A Simplified Approach to Proofs of Validity 284
The Basic Rules 285 What Is a Proof of Validity? 285 How to Construct a Proof of
Validity 286 Proofs vs. Truth Tables 287 Exercises 287 Writing Project 291
Chapter Summary 291 Key Words 292
CHAPTER 13 Categorical Propositions and Immediate Inferences 293
13.1 What Is a Categorical Proposition? 294 Categorical Propositions 294 Standard
Form 296 Non-Standard Categorical Propositions 298 Exercises 299 13.2 Venn Diagrams
for Categorical Propositions 301 Exercises 305 13.3 The Square of Opposition 308
The Traditional Square of Opposition 308 Existential Import 312 The Modern Square of
Opposition 314 Exercises 315 13.4 Other Immediate Inferences 319 Conversion 319
Obversion 320 Contraposition 322 Exercises 325 ■ Writing Project 328
■ Chapter Summary 328 • Key Words 329
(/)
f
z
w
f
z
0
0
0
w
_J
f
w
0
–
(/)
1-
z
LI.I
1-
z
0
0
0
LI.I
…J
�
LI.I
0
…
CHAPTER 14 Categorical Syllogisms 330
14.1 What Is a Categorical Syllogism? 331 The Terms of a Syllogism 331 The Premises of a
Syllogism 332 Recognizing Syllogisms 333 14.2 Syllogistic Argument Forms 335
Figure 335 Mood 336 Determining a Syllogism’s Form 337 Exercises 339 14.3 Testing for
Validity with Venn Diagrams 342 How to Diagram a Standard Syllogism 342
Exercises 351 ■ 14.4 Distribution of Terms 354 14.5 Rules of Validity and
Syllogistic Fallacies 356 Rules ofValidity vs. Venn Diagrams 359 Exercises 360 ■
Writing Project 363 ■ Chapter Summary 363 ■ Key Words 364
Solutions to Selected Exercises 365
Glossary /Index 386
Index 396
preface
This is a book intended for introductory courses in logic and critical thinking, but its scope is
broadly focused to include some issues in philosophy as well as treatments of induction,
informal fallacies, and both propositional and traditional syllogistic logic. Its aim throughout,
however, is to broach these topics in a way that will be accessible to beginners in college-level
work. How to Think Logically is a user-friendly text designed for students who have never
encountered philosophy before, and for whom a systematic approach to analytical thinking
may be an unfamiliar exercise. The writing style is simple and direct, with jargon kept to a min
imum. Symbolism is also kept simple. Scattered through the text are special-emphasis boxes in
which important points are summarized to help students focus on crucial distinctions and
fundamental ideas. The book’s fourteen chapters unfold in a way that undergraduates will find
understandable and easy to follow. Even so, the book maintains a punctilious regard for the
principles of logic. At no point does it compromise rigor.
How to Think Logically is a guide to the analysis, reconstruction, and evaluation of argu
ments. It is designed to help students learn to distinguish good reasoning from bad. The book is
divided into four parts. The first is devoted to argument recognition and the building blocks of
argument. Chapter 1 introduces argument analysis, focusing on argument recognition and the
difference between formal and informal approaches to inference. Chapter 2 offers a closer look
at the language from which arguments are constructed and examines such topics as logical
strength, linguistic merit, rhetorical power, types of sentences, uses of language, and definition.
Chapter 3 considers epistemic aspects of the statements that are the components of an inference.
It explains the assumption that when speakers are sincere and competent, what they state is what
they believe, so that the epistemic virtues and vices of belief may also affect statements. Part II is
devoted to the analysis of deductive and inductive arguments, distinguishing under each of
these two general classifications several different types of argument that students should be able
to recognize. It also includes discussions of the principles of charity and faithfulness, extended
arguments, enthymemes, and normative arguments of four different kinds. In Part III, students
are shown how some very basic confusions in thinking may lead to defective reasoning, and they
learn to spot twenty of the most common informal fallacies. Part N, which comprises Chapters 11
through 14, offers a feature many instructors will want: a detailed treatment of some common
elementary procedures for determining validity in propositional logic-including a simplified
approach to proofs-and traditional syllogistic logic. Here students will be able to go well
beyond the intuitive procedures learned in Chapter 5.
Each of the book’s four parts is a self-contained unit. The topics are presented in a way
that permits instructors to teach the chapters in different sequences and combinations,
according to the needs of their courses. For example, an instructor in a critical thinking
course could simply assign Chapters 1 through 10. But in a course geared more to deductive
xi
LU
0
<(
LL
LU
a:
a.
logic, Chapters 1, 4, 5, and 6 and then 11 through 14 might serve best. Other instructors
might want to do some of both critical thinking and deductive logic, for which the best
strategy might be to assign Chapter 1 and then either 4 through 12, or 4 through 10 plus
13 and 14.
How to Think Logically, in this new second-edition format, includes a number of
improvements, thanks to the helpful suggestions of anonymous reviewers selected by Pearson
and of philosophers we know who are using the book:
■ Chapter 1 has been reworked to present a better introduction to argument, the central
topic of the book. The treatment of non-arguments now includes entries for explanations,
conditionals, and fictional discourse.
A more concise treatment of definition now follows discussions of figurative meaning
and indirect use of language in Chapter 2. Also added to this chapter is an expanded
treatment of sentence types, including speech acts, in connection with the discussion of
uses of language, providing a more nuanced and timely treatment of this topic.
The discussions of contradiction and consistency in Chapter 3 have been rewritten for
greater clarity.
The section on evaluative reasoning in Chapter 4 has been expanded into a much
improved discussion of moral, legal, prudential, and aesthetic norms and arguments.
Many new examples, of varying degrees of difficulty, have been incorporated in the book's
account of informal fallacies. First-edition examples have been brought up to date.
Exercise sections in all chapters have been greatly expanded. Many new exercises have
been added, so that students can now get more practice in applying what they're learning.
As a result, instructors will now have a larger selection of exercises from which to choose
in assigning homework or in engaging students in class discussions.
■ The program of the book has been simplified so that it does much better, and more
economically, what instructors need it to do: namely, serve as a text for teaching
students how to develop critical-reasoning skills. The 'Philosopher's Corner' features of
the first edition have been taken out, following the consensus of reviewers, who said
that they almost never had time in a fifteen-week semester to use them if they were
teaching the logic, too. In this new edition, references to philosophical theories have
been minimized and woven into topics of informal logic. In this way, the overall length
of the book has been kept about the same as in the first edition, and the price of the
book has been kept low.
But many features of the earlier edition have been retained here. There are abundant
pedagogical aids in the book, including not only more exercises, but also study questions and
lists of key words. At the end of each chapter are a chapter summary and a writing project. And
in the back of the book is a detailed glossary of important terms.
We wish to thank our editor at Pearson Education, Nancy Roberts, and Kate Fernandes, the
project manager for this book. Special thanks are due also to Pearson editor-in-chief Dickson
Musslewhite, who provided judicious guidance at crucial points in bringing out this new
edition. We are also grateful for the criticisms of the philosophers selected as anonymous
reviewers by Pearson. Their sometimes barbed but always trenchant observations about the
first edition have helped us to make this a much better textbook.
Support for Instructors and Students
MySearchLab.com is an online tool that offers a wealth of resources to help student learning
and comprehension, including practice quizzes, primary source readings and more. Please
contact your Pearson representative for more information or visit www.MySearchLab.com
Instructor's Manual with Tests (0-205-15534-0) for each chapter in the text, this valuable
resource provides a detailed outline, list of objectives, and discussion questions. In addition,
test questions in multiple-choice, true/false, fill-in-the-blank, and short answer formats are
available for each chapter; the answers are page referenced to the text. For easy access, this
manual is available at www.pearsonhighered.com/irc.
PowerPoint Presentation Slides for How to Think Logically (0-205-15538-3): These
PowerPoint Slides help instructors convey logic principles in a clear and engaging way. For
easy access, they are available at www.pearsonhighered.com/irc.
w
0
w
a:
Q_
about the authors
GARY SEAY has taught formal and informal logic since 1979 at the
City University of New York, where he is presently professor of phi
losophy at Medgar Evers College. His articles on moral philosophy
and bioethics have appeared in The American Philosophical Q.uarter!Y,
The Journal of Value Inquiry, The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy,
and The Cambridge Q_uarter!Y of Healthcare Ethics, among other
journals. With Susana Nuccetelli, he is editor of Themes from
G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics (Oxford University
Press, 2007), Philosophy of Language: The Central Topics (Rowman and
Littlefield, 2007), and Latin American Philosophy: An Introduction with
Readings (Prentice Hall, 2004).
SUSANA NUCCETELLI is professor of philosophy at St. Cloud
State University in Minnesota. Her essays in epistemology and
philosophy of language have appeared in Anarysis, The American
Philosophical Q!iarter!Y, Metaphilosophy, The Philosophical Forum,
Inquiry, and The Southern Journal of Philosophy, among other
journals. She is editor of New Essays in Semantic Externalism and
Self-Knowledge (MIT Press, 2003) and author of Latin American
Thought: Philosophical Problems and Arguments (Westview Press,
2002). She is co-editor of The Blackwell Companion to Latin American
Philosophy (Blackwell, 2009) and, with Gary Seay, Ethical Naturalism:
Current Debates (Cambridge University Press, forthcoming, 2011).
xiv
The Building Blocks
of Reasoning
Pa rt
What Is Logical
Thinking? And
Why Should
We Care?
CHAPTER
After reading this chapter, you'll be able to answer questions about
logical thinking, such as
What is its subject matter?
■ How does its approach to reasoning differ from those of neuroscience and psychology?
■ Which are the main dimensions of logical thinking?
■ How does logical thinking differ from formal logic?
■ What is an argument? And how is it distinguished from a non-argument?
■ What are the steps in argument analysis?
3
1.1 The Study of Reasoning
Logical thinking, or informal logic, is a branch of philosophy devoted to the study of reason
ing. Although it shares this interest with other philosophical and scientific disciplines, it differs
from them in a number of ways. Compare, for example, cognitive psychology and neuro
science. These also study reasoning but are chiefly concerned with the mental and physiolog
ical processes underlying it. By contrast, logical thinking focuses on the outcomes of such
processes: namely, certain logical relations among beliefs and their building blocks that obtain
when reasoning is at work. It also focuses on logical relations among statements, which, when
speakers are sincere and competent, express the logical relations among their beliefs.
Inference or Argument
As far as logical thinking is concerned, reasoning consists in logical relations. Prominent
among them is a relation whereby one or more beliefs are taken to offer support for another.
Known as inference or argument, this relation obtains whenever a thinker entertains one or
more beliefs as being reasons in support of another belief. Inferences could be strong, weak, or
failed. Here is an example of a strong inference:
1 All whales are mammals, and Moby Dick is a whale; therefore, Moby Dick is a
mammal.
(1) is a strong inference because, if the beliefs offered as reasons ('All whales are mammals,' and
'Moby Dick is a whale') are true, then the belief they are supposed to support ('Moby Dick is a
mammal') must also be true. But compare
2 No oranges from Florida are small; therefore, no oranges from the United States
are small.
In (2) the logical relation of inference between the beliefs is weak, since the reason offered ('No
oranges from Florida are small') could be true and the belief it's offered to support ('No oranges
from the United States are small') false. But by no means does (2) illustrate the worst-case
scenario. In some attempted inferences, a belief or beliefs offered to support another belief
might fail to do so. Consider
3 No oranges are apples; therefore, all elms are trees.
Since in (3) 'therefore' occurs between the two beliefs, it is clear that 'No oranges are
apples' is offered as a reason for 'All elms are trees.' Yet it is not. Although these two beliefs
both happen to be true, they do not stand in the relation of inference. Here is another such
case of failed inference, this time involving false beliefs:
4 All lawyers are thin; therefore, the current pope is Chinese.
Since in (4) the component beliefs have little to do with each other, neither of them actually
supports the other. As in (3), the inference fails.
Success and failure in inference are logical thinking's central topic. Let's now look more
closely at how it approaches this subject.
1.2 Logic and Reasoning
Dimensions of the Subject
Inference is the most fundamental relation between beliefs or thoughts when reasoning is at
work. Logical thinking studies this and other logical relations, with an eye toward
1. Describing patterns of reasoning.
2. Evaluating good- and bad-making features of reasoning.
3. Sanctioning rules for maximizing reasoning's good-making features.
Each of these tasks may be thought of as a dimension of logical thinking. The first describes
logical relations, which initially requires identifying common patterns of inference. The
second distinguishes good and bad traits in those relations. And the third sanctions rules for
adequate reasoning. Rules are norms that can help us maximize the good (and minimize the
bad) traits of our reasoning. The picture that emerges is as in Box 1.
Understanding these dimensions is crucial to the study of reasoning. Since the third
dimension especially bears on how well we perform at reasoning, it has practical worth or cash
value. Its cash value consists in the prescriptions it issues for materially improving our reason
ing. But this dimension depends on the other two, because useful prescriptions for adequate
reasoning require accurate descriptions of the common logical relations established by
reasoning (such as inference). And they require adequate criteria to distinguish good and bad
features in those relations.
Formal Logic
What we're calling 'logical thinking' is often known as informal logic. This discipline shares
with another branch of philosophy.formal logic, its interest in inference and other logical
relations. Informal and formal logic differ, however, in their scope and methods. Formal logic
is also known as symbolic logic. It develops its own formal languages for the purpose of
BOX 1 ■ THREE MAIN TASKS OF LOGICAL THINKING
DESCRIPTIVE
DIMENSION
Studies the logical relations among
beliefs typical of reasoning
DIMENSIONS OF
LOGICAL THINKING
EVALUATIVE NORMATIVE
DIMENSION DIMENSION
Identifies good and bad Gives rules for achieving good
traits in reasoning and avoiding bad reasoning
CJ
z
z
0
(j)
< w
a:
0
z
<
0
CJ
0
_j
"!
11111
0-· ('
(') w
� �
Y'. 0
�w
2= s
_J 0
<(
_J
�6
(') I
0 (fJ _J >
en I
;= s
<( 0
Iz
s <(
-
deducing theorems from formulas accepted as axioms (in ways somewhat like mathematical
proofs). Any such system consists of basic symbolic expressions, the initial vocabulary of the
formal language, and rules for operations with them. The rules prescribe how to form correct
expressions and how to determine which formulas are the logical consequence of other
formulas. In formal logic, then, inference is a relation among formulas: one that holds when
ever a formula follows from one or more formulas. Formal logic uses a symbolic notation,
which may be quite complex. And its formulas need not be translated into a natural language,
which is the language of a speech community, such as English, Arabic, or Japanese. As far as
formal logic is concerned, inference is a relation among formulas. It need be neither a relation
among beliefs nor one among statements. Furthermore, it need not be identified with
inferences people actually make in ordinary reasoning.
Informal Logic
In contrast to formal logic, logical thinking is completely focused on the study of logical
relations as they occur when ordinary reasoning is at work. Its three dimensions can be shown
relevant to reasoning in a variety of common contexts, as when we deliberate about issues
such as those in Box 2.
The study of the inferences we make in these and other issues is approached by logical
thinking in its three dimensions: once it describes the logical relations underlying particular
inferences, it evaluates them and determines whether they conform to rules of good reason
ing. Since doing this requires no formal languages, logical thinking is sometimes known as
'informal logic.' Although this discipline may introduce special symbols, it need not do so: it
can be conducted entirely in a natural language. Furthermore, in contrast to formal logic, what
we're here calling 'logical thinking' approaches the study of inference as a relation among
beliefs-or among statements, the linguistic expressions of beliefs.
Why, then, should we care about logical thinking? First, we want to avoid false beliefs and
have as many true beliefs as possible, all related in a way that makes logical sense, and logical
thinking is instrumental in achieving this goal. Second, for the intellectually curious, learning
BOX 2 ■ SOME PRACTICAL USES OF LOGICAL THINKING
A criminal trial:
A domestic question:
A scientific puzzle:
A philosophical issue:
An ethical problem:
A political decision:
A financial decision:
A health matter:
Is the defendant guilty?What shall we make of the alibi?
What's the best school for our kids? Should they go to a private school,
or a public school?
How to choose between equal!), supported,yet opposite, scientific
theories?
Are mind and body the same thing, or different?
Is euthanasia moral!}, right?What about abortion?
Whom should I vote for in the general election?
Shall I follow my broker's advice and invest in this new fund?
Given my medical records, is exercise good for me? Do I need more health
insurance?
about the logical relations that take place in reasoning is an activity worthwhile for its own
sake. Moreover, it can help us in practical situations where competent reasoning is required,
which are exceedingly common. They arise whenever we wish to do well in intellectual
tasks such as those listed in Box 2. Each of us has faced them at some point-for example,
in attempting to convince someone of a view, in writing on a controversial topic, or simply in
deciding between two seemingly well-supported yet incompatible claims. To succeed in
meeting these ordinary challenges requires the ability to think logically. In the next section,
we'll have a closer look at this important competence.
Exercises
1. How does logical thinking differ from scientific disciplines that study reasoning?
2. What is informal logic? And how does it differ from formal logic?
3. What is the main topic of logical thinking?
4. List one feature that logical thinking and formal logic have in common and one about which they
differ.
5. What is an inference?
6. Could an inference fail completely? If so, how? If not, why not?
7. What are the different dimensions of logical thinking?
8. Which dimension of logical thinking is relevant to determining reasoning's good- and bad-making
traits?
9. Which is the dimension of logical thinking that has "cash value"? And what does this mean?
10. What is a natural language? Give three examples of a natural language.
II. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1 . Construct two inferences.
2. Construct a strong inference (one in which, if the supporting beliefs are true, the supported belief
must be true).
3. Construct a weak inference (one in which the supporting beliefs could be true and the belief they're
intended to support false).
4. Construct a blatantly failed inference.
5. Describe a scenario for which logical thinking could help a thinker in everyday life.
6. Describe a scenario for which logical thinking could help with your own studies in college.
7. Suppose someone says, "Thinking logically has no practical worth!" How would you respond?
8. 'Cats are carnivorous animals. No carnivorous animals are vegetarians; therefore, no cat is a vegetarian'
is a strong inference. Why?
9. Consider 'All geckos are nocturnal. Therefore, there will be peace in the Middle East next year.'
What's the matter with this inference?
10. Consider 'Politicians are all crooks. Therefore, it never snows in the Sahara.' What's the matter with
this inference?
(')
z
z
0
Cl)
<(
L.IJ
0:
0
z
<(
0
(')
0
_j
�
-
C'-- C'-
('J w
z a: - <1'.
�o
�w
i: �
_J 0
<1'.
_J
S:? 6 ('J I
0 (/)
_J
>
(/) I
;=:�
<1'. 0
Iz
� <1'.
-
1.3 What Arguments Are
In this book, we call 'inference' the relation whereby one or more beliefs are taken to support
another belief, and 'argument' the relation whereby one or more statements are offered in
support of another statement. When speakers are sincere and competent, they believe what
they assert, and their statements express their beliefs. Thus 'inference' and 'argument' may be
taken to apply to the same relation. Just as beliefs are the fundamental parts, or building
blocks, of inference, so statements are the building blocks from which arguments are con
structed. A statement is like a belief, in that it has a truth value, which is a way of saying that it
is either true ('No apples are oranges') or false ('The Pope is Chinese').
But not all relations between statements constitute arguments. Suppose someone says:
5 Philadelphia is a large city, and Chicago is larger still, but New York is the largest
of all.
Although (s) is made up of three simple statements grouped together, it does not amount to an
argument, for there is no attempt at presenting a supported claim; that is, the statements are
not arranged so that one of them makes a claim for which the others are offered as reasons.
Rather, they are just three conjoined statements. By contrast,
6 I think, therefore I am.
7 All lawyers are attorneys. Jack McCoy is a lawyer. Thus Jack McCoy is an attorney.
8 No chiropractors are surgeons. Only surgeons can legally perform a coronary bypass.
Hence, no chiropractors can legally perform a coronary bypass.
9 A Chevrolet Impala is faster than a bicycle. A Maserati is faster than a Chevrolet
Impala. A Japanese bullet train is faster than a Maserati. It follows that a Japanese
bullet train is faster than a bicycle.
In each of these examples, a claim is made and at least one other statement is offered in
support of that claim. This is the basic feature that all arguments share: every argument must
BOX 3 ■ THE BUILDING BLOCKS OF ARGUMENT
• Statements are the building blocks of argument
• They have truth values, because they express beliefs, and beliefs also have truth values
• Each statement is either true or false
• Only sentences that can be used to express beliefs can be used to make statements
• Sentences of the following
types cannot be used to make
statements
•1. Expressive sentences (e.g., "What a lovely day!")
•2. Imperative sentences (e.g., "Please close the door")
•3. Interrogative sentences ("What did you do last weekend?'') More
on this in Chapter 2
consist of at least two statements, one that makes a claim of some sort, and one or more others
that are offered in support of it. The statement that makes the claim is the conclusion, and that
offered to support it is the premise (or premises, if there are more than one).
Now, clearly we are introducing some special terminology here. For in everyday English, 'argu
ment' most often means 'dispute,' a hostile verbal exchange between two or more people. But that is
very different from the more technical use of 'argument' in logical thinking, where its meaning is
similar to that common in a court of law. In a trial, each attorney is expected to present an argument.
This amounts to making a claim (e.g., 'My client is innocent') and then giving some reasons to
support it ('He was visiting his mother on the night of the crime'). In doing this, the attorney is not
having a dispute with someone in the courtroom; rather, she is making an assertion and offering
evidence that supposedly backs it up. This is very much like what we mean by 'argument' in logical
thinking. An argument is a group of statements that are intended to make a supported claim. By this
definition, then, an argument is not a verbal confrontation between two hostile parties.
Before we look more closely at argument, let's consider Box 4, which summarizes what we
already know about this relation among statements.
BOX 4 ■ SECTION SUMMARY
■ In logical thinking, the meaning of the term 'argument' is similar to that common in a
court of law.
■ For a set of statements to be an argument, one of them must be presented as supported by
the other or others.
■ An argument is a logical relation between two or more statements: a conclusion that
makes a claim of some sort, and one or more premises that are the reasons offered to
support that claim.
Argument Analysis
One essential competence that all logical thinkers must have is the ability to analyze
arguments, a technique summarized in Box 5. What, exactly, is required for this competence? It
involves knowing
1. How to recognize arguments,
2. How to identify the logical relation between their parts, and
3. How to evaluate arguments.
Recognizing an argument requires identifying the logical relations among the statements that
make it up, which is essential to the process of reconstructing an argument. Reconstruction
begins by paying close attention to the piece of spoken or written language that might contain
an argument. One must read a passage carefully or listen attentively in order to determine
whether or not a claim is being made, with reasons offered in support of it. If we have identified
a conclusion and at least one premise, we can then be confident that the passage does contain
an argument. The next step is to put the parts of the argument into an orderly arrangement, so
that the relation between premise/s and conclusion becomes plain.
LU
a:
<(
(/)
f
z
LU
�
:::)
(')
a:
<(
�
-
C'- C'C) LU
z a: -
(/) I
;::: s
(/) I
;::: 3
(/) I
;:: s
for premise indicators and square brackets ‘[ ]’ for conclusion indicators.
1. SAMPLE:
Franz, is a Doberman), [it follows that] Franz is dangerous.
2. Reverend Sharpton has no chance of being elected this time, because his campaign is not well
financed , and any politician who is not well financed has no real chance of being elected.
*3. Badgers are native to southern Wisconsin. After all, they are always spotted there.
4. Since all theoretical physicists have studied quadratic equations, no theoretical physicists are
dummies at math, for no one who has studied quadratic equations is a dummy at math.
5. Thousands of salamanders have been observed by naturalists and none has ever been found to be
warm-blooded. We may conclude that no salamanders are warm-blooded animals.
*6. In the past, every person who ever lived did eventually die. This suggests that all human beings are
mortal.
7. Since architects regularly study engineering, Frank Gehry did, for he is an architect.
8. Britney Spears’s new CD is her most innovative album so far. It’s got the best music of any new pop
music CD this year, and all the DJs are playing it on radio stations across the United States.
Accordingly, Britney Spears’s new CD is sure to win an award this year.
*9. Online education is a great option for working adults in general, regardless of their ethnic back
ground. For one thing, there is a large population of working adults who simply are not in a position
to attend a traditional university.
10. Any airline that can successfully pass some of the increases in costs on to its passengers will be able
to recover from higher fuel costs. South Airlink Airlines seems able to successfully pass some of the
increases in costs on to its passengers. As a result, South Airlink Airlines will remain in business.
11. Jackrabbits can be found in Texas. Jackrabbits are speedy rodents. Hence, some speedy rodents
can be found in Texas.
*12. There is evidence that galaxies are flying outward and apart from each other, so the cosmos will grow
darker and colder.
13. The Cubans are planning to boycott the conference, so the Venezuelans will boycott it, too.
14. Since Reverend Windfield will preach an extra-long sermon this Sunday, we may therefore expect
that some of his congregation will fall asleep.
*15. Captain Binnacle will not desert his sinking ship, for only a cowardly captain would desert a sinking
ship, and Captain Binnacle is no coward.
16. A well-known biologist recently admitted having fabricated data on stem-cell experiments. So his
claim that he has a cloned dog is probably false.
17. The French minister of culture has announced that France will not restrict American movies.
Assuming that film critics are right in questioning the overall quality of American movies, it follows that
French movie theaters will soon feature movies of questionable quality.
*18. The University of California at Berkeley is strong in math, for many instructors in its Math Department
have published breakthrough papers in the core areas of mathematics.
19. Her Spanish must be good now. She spent a year in Mexico living with a Mexican family, and she
took courses at the Autonomous University of Mexico.
(j)
f
z
LU
�
🙂
(.’J
a:
�
(.’J
z
f-
0
🙂
a:
f
(j)
z
0
0
LU
a:
�
<:--· <:--·
0W
��
;,:'. (.)
�w
�s
___J 0
<( ___J
(.) ::J -0
0I
0 (J)
___J >
(J) I
;= s
<( 0
Iz
s <(
11111
*20. No one who knowingly and needlessly endangers his or her life is rational. Thus college students who
smoke are not rational, because every college student who smokes is knowingly and unnecessarily
endangering his or her life.
21. The next major earthquake that hits California will be more devastating than the great San Francisco
earthquake of 1906, because there are many more people in California now than there were then,
and the urban concentration along the San Andreas Fault is much greater today.
22. Isaac Newton was one of the greatest physicists of all time. After all, he was the discoverer of the law
of gravity.
23. Maestro von Umlaut will not continue in his post as music director of the Philharmonic, since con
ductors of important orchestras can continue in that post only as long as they deliver great perform
ances, and in the last ten years, von Umlaut has not delivered great performances.
24. Mayor Wilson will have to make a strong campaign for reelection next year. He lost popularity as a re
sult of his position on immigration.
*25. Given that all Athenians are Greeks and that Plato was an Athenian, we may infer that Plato was a Greek.
VI. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. Construct two arguments, one in favor of legalized abortion, the other against it.
2. What's the matter with accepting the two arguments proposed for (1) at once?
3. Construct two arguments: one for the conclusion that God exists, and one for the conclusion that
God doesn't exist.
4. Some people argue that the death penalty is morally appropriate as a punishment for murder, but
others argue for the opposite view. For which of these two positions might it be appropriate to use as
a premise 'Murderers deserve to die'?
5. Construct a strong argument with the premises 'People who commit crimes deserve punishment'
and 'The defendant committed a crime,' listing its parts in logical order.
1.5 Arguments and Non-arguments
Explanations
We've seen that an argument can be distinguished from other logical relations among state
ments chiefly by asking whether it offers some statement(s) in support of a claim. If not,
then it's not an argument but something else! We've also seen that there are some helpful
words and phrases that often point to the presence of an argument, since they could be of
help in spotting premises and conclusions. The trouble is, some of these same words and
phrases-words like 'because,' 'since,' and 'as a result'-often appear in explanations, which
many philosophers think are not arguments at all. For our purposes here, we'll assume only
that explanations are different enough from arguments that logical thinkers need a reliable
way to tell the difference.
Explanations often bear a superficial resemblance to arguments, owing to the fact that
each is a type of relation among statements in which one or more of them are supposed to give
reasons for another statement, which is the claim that's being made. But the reasons are of very
different kinds in argument and explanation.
1. In arguments, the reasons (premises) are offered to back up a claim (conclusion) that
the arguer considers in need of support.
2. In explanations, reasons are offered to account for the events or states of affairs
described by a claim that the arguer takes to be not in need of support.
Consider these relations among statements:
17 The stock market crashed in 2008 because large banks made reckless home mortgage
loans that proved uncollectable, and investors lost confidence in a broad range of
securities traded on major stock exchanges.
18 The stock market is not a realistic environment for the small investor, because such
investors are unlikely to assume the level of risk that can lead to substantial gains,
and market volatility brings the ever-present danger of ruin for those without sizable
cash reserves.
Examples (17) and (18) both make use of the word 'because,' which is often a premise indica
tor. But it has that function in on!), one of these two examples. Can you see which one? It's (18), for
(18) features reasons offered in support of the argument's conclusion. In (17), the arguer already
accepts that the stock market crashed in 2008 and offers explanatory reasons to account for that
event. Notice that in (18), the conclusion comes at the beginning-the claim that 'The stock
market is not a realistic environment for the small investor'-and then two other statements
offer reasons why we should accept that claim as true. (Is the claim true? It may be true. Or
maybe not! We need not take a stand on that! We know that it's the conclusion of an argument,
because it's offered by the arguer as being supported by the argument's premises.)
By contrast, in (17), the explanation begins with a statement that is accepted by the arguer
as a fact: 'The stock market crashed in 2008.' The other two statements serve not to give
reasons why we should accept the first statement (after all, we don't need to be convinced that
the market crashed in 2008�, but only reasons to account for why that event occurred.
Arguments and explanations, then, could each be thought of as a logical relation between
statements. In the case of argument, the relation is between some claim and the statement/s that
are supposed to provide reasons for accepting it as true; in the case of explanation, the relation is
between a claim that the thinker has already accepted as true and the statement/s that are offered
to give an account of why or how it came to be true. In light of this, explanations can be thought
of as distinct from arguments, and it's important to be able to tell the difference.
Conditionals
Explanations are not the only logical relation apt to be confused with arguments. Another is
that often expressed by 'if . . . then .. . ' sentences, which are used to make compound
statements called 'conditionals.' We'll later discuss them at some length. For our purposes
here, it suffices to keep in mind that although they may be part of an argument (in fact, this
(j)
1-
z
w
::?
::J
(.'J
a:
(j) I
;:::: 5
<( 0
Iz
5 <(
-
*16. If judges were strict with criminals, then all offenses would be punished. But some offenses are not
punished. So, judges are not strict with criminals.
17. It occurred to me that because twins are genetically identical, their sons are actually half brothers!
*18. Since I went on my first date in high school, more than two hundred species of frogs have
disappeared forever.
19. The Mississippi River rises in the lake country of northern Minnesota and flows southward all the way
to the Gulf of Mexico. Over the course of this great distance, it divides the eastern watershed of the
United States from the western and drains all the rivers for hundreds of miles in both directions in the
middle of the continent.
*20. Superman cost more than $200 million. Most movies that cost more than $200 million do well. It
follows that Superman will do well.
21. If Harry Potter is a fictional character, then he cannot vote in England.
22. Tracey will do well on her MEDCAT exams. People who get straight A's in their science courses often
do well on MEDCAT exams, and she got straight A's in hers.
23. If hydrogen is the lightest element, then hydrogen is lighter than oxygen.
24. Dolphins are mammals, and whales are mammals, but sharks are a species of fish.
25. The nation's major banks, placing the blame on their own higher costs for borrowed money,
raised their prime lending rate yesterday to 13 percent, from 12 percent. The increase sent
the prime, the rate charged by banks to their best corporate customers, to its highest level since
mid-June.
VIII. In each passage above containing an argument, underline the conclusion and
mark the premises with parentheses.
IX. Each of the passages below is either an argument or an explanation. Say which
is which.
1. She will soon date someone else. Edgar is never fashionably dressed, and her mother would prefer
her having a fashionably dressed boyfriend.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Argument.
2. Pacifists shouldn't serve in the military. The reason for this is that pacifists believe that all wars are
wrong, and the military often engages in wars.
3. Henry always votes in elections, because he believes that it's his duty as a citizen to do so.
*4. Christine is the Green Party nominee for the U.S. Senate, so we can be sure that she cares about the
environment.
5. Either matter has always existed in some form, or the universe came into being out of nothing. But
since it's inconceivable that something like the universe came into existence out of nothing, it follows
that matter must have always existed in some form.
*6. There was a lot of humidity in the atmosphere yesterday, but at dusk a cold air mass moved in from
the west. As a result, there were thunderstorms.
7. Senator Smith knew that his chief of staff sent a memo implicating the senator in a sex scandal.
After all, the chief of staff was fired the very same day that news of the scandal broke on the NBC
Nightly News.
8. Man tends to increase at a greater rate than his means of subsistence; consequently, he is occasionally
subject to a severe struggle for existence. (Charles Darwin, The Descent of Man)
*9. Scotland Yard publicly alleged that a member of the Russian intelligence service was responsible for
poisoning a former KGB spy. This suggests that there will be some tense exchanges between
Britain's Foreign Office and the Russian Foreign Ministry.
*10. Speculators have been driving up the cost of real-estate downtown. As a result, hardly any middle-class
families can afford to live there now.
X. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1 . Construct an argument of your own with premise and conclusion indicators, marking these as in
Exercise V.
2. Construct an argument of your own without premise and conclusion indicators, underlining its conclusion
and marking its premises with parentheses.
3. Find an explanation and say why it is not an argument.
4. Construct a conditional of your own and say why it is not an argument.
■ Writing Project
Select a claim you feel very strongly about and write a short essay explaining what you take to
be the best reasons for that claim. For further work, keep this essay on file, and go back to it for
a critical assessment at the end of this course. By the way, never forget to give full references
for your sources of information, if you use any! (Length: about two pages, double-spaced, or as
directed by your instructor.)
■ Chapter Summary
Logical or critical thinking: informal logic. It studies reasoning, but it is
Not concerned with brain processes.
Not concerned with cause-effect explanations.
Concerned with the logical relations that obtain when reasoning is at work.
Why be logical thinkers?
Two fundamental goals:
■ To have true beliefs and avoid false ones.
■ To upgrade the set of beliefs we already have by acquiring new true beliefs and avoiding
false ones.
>
a:
<(
�
�
::i
(j)
a:
w
f--
0..
<(
I
0
BIi
C'-· c--
('.) w
� �
�o
�w
� s
_J 0
<( _J
S:2 6
('.) I
0 (j)
_J >
(j) I
;= s
<( 0
Iz
s <(
11111&1
Situations where careful reasoning is required:
■ Supporting our beliefs
■ Acquiring new, supported beliefs
■ Persuading others of our beliefs
■ Putting various pieces of information together in a way that makes sense
■ Deciding between opposite views
■ Avoiding common mistakes in reasoning
■ Questioning beliefs that may be mistaken, make no sense, or lack
adequate evidence
Dimensions of logical thinking:
1. Descriptive: it identifies patterns of logical relation such as inference.
2. Evaluative: it determines which patterns are good and which are bad.
3. Nonnative: it formulates rules to maximize good reasoning and minimize bad.
Statement: True or false sentence that expresses a thought or belief.
Inference: One or more beliefs taken to support another belief.
Argument: One or more statements taken to support another statement. Arguments
express inferences.
Argument analysis: argument reconstruction and argument evaluation.
How to reconstruct an argument:
A. Begin by examining a passage carefully. Distinguish arguments from non-arguments.
Keep in mind that, to be an argument at all, a passage must make a claim and offer some
reason/s for it. Identify the argument, if any. Once you've done this, move to (b).
B. Identify premise/s and conclusion. Premise and conclusion indicators, if available, can
help you here, so you should look for them first; if there are any, they will usually reveal
the premise/s and conclusion. But if there aren't any, ask yourself, 'What claim is being
made?' The answer will be the argument's conclusion. If there is a claim, then ask yourself,
'What are the reason/s offered for it?' The answer will be the argument's premise/s. Once
you have identified premise/s and conclusion, move to (c).
C. List the parts of the argument in order, premise/s first and conclusion last, separated by
a horizontal line.
The following are NOT arguments:
Passages in fictional discourse, such as that of novels, short stories, plays, song lyrics, and
poetry.
■ Explanations, where some statements are offered to make another statement understandable
or to account for its truth.
■ Conditionals, which are usually expressed by 'if ... then ... ' sentences.
■ Key Words
Inference
Informal logic
Formal logic
Argument
Argument analysis
Premise
Conclusion
Premise and conclusion indicators
Statement
Natural language
Conditional
Explanation
(/)
0
er
0
s:
>
w
CHAPTER
Thinking Logically
and Speaking
One’s Mind
In this chapter you’ll learn about some matters of concern in logical thinking, and also about
some aspects of natural language that can affect arguments. Major topics are
■ Rational acceptability and how this depends on logical connections and evidential support.
The distinction between truth and evidence.
The irrelevance of linguistic merit and rhetorical power in weighing rational acceptability.
The role of propositions as the contents of beliefs and statements.
The uses of language in connection with four basic categories of speech act.
Four types of sentence and their relation to the basic uses of language.
How to distinguish between direct and indirect language, and between literal and figurative uses
of language.
Definition as an antidote to unclear language.
24
2.1 Rational Acceptability
Logical Connectedness
Acceptable thinking requires logical connectedness and the support of reasons. Salient among
logical connections is that of argument, which obtains when at least one statement is offered
as being supported by others. In argument, the strength of the logical connection between
premises and conclusion is proportional to the strength of the argument itself: the more
logical connectedness among its parts, the stronger the argument. And since statements are
the expressions of beliefs, the same could be said of belief and inference. Consider,
1 That smoking is linked to early lung disease argues against smoking.
(1) contains remarks about the logical relation between premises (that smoking is linked to
early lung disease) and a conclusion (which we may paraphrase as ‘people should not smoke’).
Such remarks point to the feature we are calling ‘logical connectedness.’ Similarly, logical
connectedness is alluded to when we say that a certain statement is a premise, a reason, a
conclusion, or follows from another.
Logical connectedness is a matter of degree: some relations among beliefs might have it
absolutely, others only in part. In addition, some groups of beliefs may lack it entirely.
For example,
2 Florida is on the Gulf of Mexico. Any state on the Gulf of Mexico has mild winters.
Therefore, Florida has mild winters.
(2) has a high degree of logical connectedness, since its premises support its conclusion
strongly: if they are true, the conclusion has to be true. By contrast, (3) has a low degree of
logical connectedness, for it is a weak argument, in the sense that, although its premises are
true, its conclusion could be false.
3 Florida has mild winters, and so do Hawaii and Texas; therefore, most U.S. states
have mild winters.
Now consider an argument whose premise and conclusion have no logical connectedness
at all:
4 Florida is a subtropical state on the Gulf of Mexico; therefore, computers have
replaced typewriters.
(2), (3), and (4) illustrate decreasing degrees of logical connectedness. (2) has the highest degree
of logical connectedness. Logical thinkers who recognize this, together with the fact that (2)’s
premises seem true, cannot reject (2)’s conclusion without a serious failure of reasoning.
Logical connectedness partly determines whether an argument is rationally acceptable-that
is, whether it counts as acceptable reasoning. Neither (3) nor (4) qualifies as rationally acceptable:
(3) lacks a sufficient degree of logical connectedness, and (4) doesn’t have it at all. Neither is a
model of the sort of reasoning logical thinkers ought to engage in.
Beliefs with a good share of logical connectedness are the kind of reasoning we ought to
engage in-provided that they also meet other conditions, such as being based on solid
>
t:
….J
(!)
<(
r-
0..
w
0
0
<(
....J
<(
z
0
N
CJ z
::.::
<(
w
a..
(/)
0
z
<(
<(
CJ
So
CJ �
z�
� (/)
z UJ
:i:Z
r-0
BOX 1 ■ LOGICAL CONNECTEDNESS AND INFERENCE
■ The rational acceptability of an argument depends on its logical connectedness, and also on
whether any premise in need of evidential support in fact has it.
■ The logical connectedness of an argument resides in the relation between its premises and
conclusion. Any deficiency in logical connectedness would undermine an argument's rational
acceptability.
reasons or evidence. Acceptable arguments are crucial to our ability to think logically.
Furthermore, when an argument is used to persuade ( e.g., to convince an audience or win a
debate), any deficiency in rational acceptability would make it vulnerable to objections.
Evidential Support
The rational acceptability of many beliefs depends on evidence, which is information obtained
from observation, whether one's own or that of reliable sources. Beliefs of that sort are
empirical and are supported when the total evidence points to their being true. The 'total
evidence' for a belief includes all relevant information available to the thinker at a time:
evidence for the belief, and also evidence against it. Thus the total evidence for a belief requires
careful consideration of any information pointing to its being false, as well as information
pointing to its being true. The total evidence, then, is the result of "factoring in" partial
evidence of both kinds. When a belief is empirical, the upshot of considering the total
evidence is one of the following:
Scenario
Most of the relevant evidence points to a belief's
being true.
II Most of the relevant evidence points to a belief's
being false.
III The evidence is "split," equally pointing to a belief's
being true and to its being false.
➔
➔
➔
Evidential-Support Status
The belief is supported
by the evidence
The belief is undermined
by the evidence
The belief is not supported
by the evidence
Only beliefs that fall within category (I) may be said to be 'supported by the evidence.'
Note that although both logical connectedness and evidential support are needed for
rational acceptability, they are independent of each other. After all, any piece of reasoning
could have one without having the other. For example,
5 Anyone who breaks a mirror will have seven years' bad luck. Today I broke a mirror.
Therefore, I'll have seven years' bad luck.
(s) has logical connectedness, since if its premises are true, its conclusion is also true. Yet we
now know that the evidence does not support one of the premises: that anyone who breaks a
mirror will have seven years' bad luck. As a result, (s) falls short of being a rationally acceptable
argument.
When engaging in reasoning, at all times
■ Maximize the logical connectedness among beliefs.
■ Favor beliefs supported by the evidence.
Truth and Evidence
What matters for the evidential support of a belief is not that it is true, but rather that the
total evidence available to the thinker points to its being true. This allows for a range of
combinations. To begin with, a false belief could be supported by the evidence. Consider
6 The earth does not revolve.
For people in the Middle Ages, this belief was supported by the evidence. As far as they could
tell, the belief was true (all information then available pointed to its being true). Yet (6) was
false, and those people were therefore in error. At the same time, a true belief could fail to be
supported by the evidence, as was (7) before the twentieth century, when there was not enough
evidence pointing to the existence of atoms.
7 There are atoms.
Truth and evidence, then, are different concepts that must not be confused. Truth concerns
how things are. A belief is true if and only if things actually are as represented by it. Evidence
involves the information about how things are that is available to thinkers-which could turn
out to be misleading or even false. Of the two, it is only evidence that bears on rational accept
ability. This does not undermine the importance of truth, however, which is arguably desirable
for its own sake, given that humans seem to be, by nature, intellectually curious beings.
BOX 2 ■ SECTION SUMMARY
RATIONAL
ACCEPTABILITY
LOGICAL
CONNECTEDNESS
It concerns the strength of
the relation of inference
EVIDENTIAL
SUPPORT
It concerns the relevant
information available to the thinker
>
!:::
co
t:
0)
LU
0)
N
N
II. Determine whether the following statements bear on logical connectedness,
evidential support, linguistic merit, rhetorical power, or a combination of some
of these.
� 1. The Declaration of Independence has just the right words and makes claims that are backed up
� by reasons.
� SAMPLE ANSWER: linguistic merit and logical connectedness
0
z 2. The observation points to the truth of Galileo’s law of falling bodies.
<(
<(
So
CD�
22
� (j)
z UJ
:r:Z
I- 0
1111D
*3. The speaker was well dressed and spoke with the right voice and gestures.
4. The fossil record favors neither evolution nor creation.
*5. The fossil record favors evolution.
6. He is a lousy speaker, in that he always uses ungrammatical language. Besides, he is insecure.
On top of it, he never looks at you when he speaks.
7. The belief that some mammals are whales is strongly supported by the belief that all whales are
mammals. If the latter is true, the former must be true.
*8. It makes no sense to think that Ellen is an ophthalmologist but not an eye doctor. From the fact that she
is an ophthalmologist, it follows that she is an eye doctor. After all, "ophthalmologist" means 11eye doc
tor."
9. After seeing him so devastated, I became totally convinced of his story.
*10. The ideas were poorly phrased, in a heavily accented language. Almost a dialect.
*11. Had you been in court this morning, you'd have been persuaded by the prosecutor's stern attitude.
*12. That the butler has an alibi offers some support to the conclusion that he did not do it. But couldn't
that conclusion be false even if he does have an alibi?
13. The conclusion that someone is a male sibling follows necessarily from the premise that he is a
brother.
14. Magellan's voyage provided empirical data that proved that the Earth is not flat. If the Earth were
flat, Magellan's ship couldn't have circumnavigated it. From this, we cannot but conclude that the
Earth is not flat.
*15. She couldn't have found better words to make her point succinctly.
Ill. Each characteristic on the left falls under one of the four standards on the right.
Pair them accordingly.
1. Being prolix in language
SAMPLE ANSWER: Linguistic merit
*2. Having good manners
3. Being concise
*4. Finding fingerprints at the scene of a crime
5. Persuading the audience
A. Logical connectedness
B. Evidential support
*6. Following from some premises C. Linguistic merit
7. Citing the report of a reliable witness D. Rhetorical power
*8. Having a direct visual experience
9. Being inferred from other beliefs
*10. Being strongly inferred from other beliefs
11. Failing to be inferred from other beliefs
*12. Having nervous mannerisms in speech
IV. Determine whether the logical connectedness in each of the following arguments
is strong, weak, or failed. Use these criteria: If the conclusion must be true if the
premises are true, the connection is strong; if the conclusion is somewhat
supported by the premises but it could be false even if the premises are true, the
connection is weak; and if premises and conclusion are not related at all, the
connection is failed.
1. Columbus was married. Therefore, Columbus wasn't single.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Strong logical connectedness
2. Pierre is French. Therefore, he is European.
*3. The Yucatan ruins are well preserved. Therefore, Yucatan is worth visiting.
4. Triangles have three internal angles. Isosceles triangles are triangles. Therefore, cats are feline.
5. My dog, Fido, barks. Therefore, all dogs bark.
*6. She is the string quartet's first violinist. Therefore, she is a musician.
7. The house is now finished. Therefore, a tennis match is going on.
8. A loud sound broke the calm of night. Therefore, there was some thunder.
*9. No candies are nutritious. Therefore, nutritious things are not delicious.
10. We visit only cities that have mild weather. Last year we visited Miami and San Diego. Therefore,
these cities have mild weather.
V. Determine whether each of the following scenarios is possible or impossible.
For each one that is impossible, explain why.
1. A group of statements that is logically connected and it isn't.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Impossible. This scenario makes two opposite claims at once.
2. A statement for which the evidence is split: half supports it, the other half undermines it.
*3. A rationally acceptable group of statements that conflicts with the available evidence.
4. A rationally acceptable group of statements that has logical connectedness.
5. A rationally acceptable group of statements without rhetorical power.
>
r—
….J
CD
w
CJ
z
�
<(
w
Q.
(j)
0
z
<
<
CJ
So
CJ �
z�
� (j)
z w
:r:Z
I- 0
*6. A rhetorically powerful group of statements that has linguistic merit.
7. A group of statements that has logical connectedness and evidential support but lacks
rational acceptability.
*8. A poorly phrased passage that has linguistic merit.
9. A rationally unacceptable inference that lacks rhetorical power.
*10. An unpersuasive speech that has rhetorical power.
11. A speech that has neither linguistic merit nor rhetorical power.
12. A passage that is neither rationally acceptable nor rhetorically powerful.
*13. A passage that has rhetorical power.
14. A false statement that is supported by the evidence.
*15. A true statement that is unsupported by the evidence.
VI. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1 . Provide a statement that is supported by the current total evidence.
2. Provide an example of a statement that is false but was once supported by the total evidence.
3. Provide an example of a statement that is true but was once unsupported by the total evidence.
4. Provide an example of a statement that has been undermined by the scientific evidence available
today.
5. Suppose you believe that there is a party in the street, but, unknown to you, your belief is false.
Provide a scenario in which that belief would nonetheless be supported by the evidence.
2.3 From Mind to Language
Propositions
We've already seen that inference is the logical relation that obtains whenever at least one
belief is taken to support another, and that it can also be conceived as a logical relation that
obtains whenever one or more statements are offered in support of another. When thus
considered, inference is often called "argument." Any argument, then, is the linguistic
expression of an inference. As beliefs are the parts that make up inferences, so statements are
the parts that make up arguments.
Now, what, exactly, are statements? Roughly, they are the standard way to express one's
beliefs by means of language, provided one is sincere and competent. Consider
8 Snow is white.
When someone accepts (8) in thought, that thinker entertains the belief that snow is white.
The standard way to express this belief would be to say that snow is white. Whether as a belief
in the mind, or put into words in a statement, (8) has the content
9 That snow is white.
(9) represents snow as being in a certain way (white). This content is complete, in the sense that
it represents a state of affairs, and if snow is as represented, then (9) is true-and if not, (9) is
false. Contents of this sort are called 'propositions.' They are true when things are as
represented by them and false when they are not. Since any belief or statement has a
proposition as its content, it also has one or the other of two truth values:
Any belief or statement is either true or false.
This is clearly illustrated by (9), whose truth value is determined by applying the following
rule: (9) is true if and only if snow is white, and it is false otherwise. For the content of each belief
or statement we are considering, we may formulate its truth conditions in the same manner.
Thus propositions may be said to have truth conditions, which are the conditions that
have to be met for a proposition to be true. Compare concepts, which are also contents but have
no truth conditions. For example,
10 Snow.
By contrast with (9), (10) is incomplete, in the sense that it is neither true nor false. Its truth
value cannot be determined because (10) lacks truth conditions: what would be the conditions
that (10) has to meet in order to be true? No truth-condition rule similar to that in Box 3 can be
offered for isolated concepts, which accordingly have no truth values (i.e., they are neither true
nor false). Although isolated concepts can be considered proposition parts, they do not count
as propositions.
Note also that when different statements have one and the same information content,
they all express the same proposition. Since in any such case the statements would represent
the same state of affairs, they would have the same truth conditions. For example, Spanish and
French translations of (8) above would be different statements, because the sentences used to
make these then would be different-namely,
11 La nieve es blanca.
12 La neige est blanche.
Yet (8), (11), and (12) have the same content, thus expressing the same proposition, (9) above.
Uses of Language
By using language we perform speech acts, which are the things we can do simply by uttering
(saying or writing) certain words: accepting or rejecting propositions, asking questions,
making promises and requests, expressing our feelings, greeting, apologizing, voting, and
many more. Speech acts can be classified according to how we intend our utterances to be
A proposition is true if and only if things are as represented by it, and it's false otherwise.
w
Cl
<(
🙂
Cl
z
<(
_J
0
l-
o
z
�
�
0
a:
LL
"'.
N
IDIII
understood by an audience. We use language primarily to (A) represent the facts, (B) get the
audience to do something, (C) express our own mental world, or (D) show our commitment to
bringing about certain states of affairs. Accordingly, our expressions fall primarily within the
(.') four categories below, each comprising many speech acts.
z
�
<(
LU
o_
(/)
0
z
<(
�
_J
<(
0
(.')
So
(.') �
z�
Q (/)
Zw
:rZ
f- 0
A. INFORMATIVES: claiming, asserting, affirming, reporting, stating, denying,
announcing, identifying, informing, predicting, answering, describing, and so on.
Example: the speech act of claiming that the defendant was involved in the crime.
B. DIRECTIVES: prescribing, asking, advising, admonishing, entreating, begging, dismiss
ing, excusing, forbidding, permitting, instructing, ordering, requesting, requiring, sug
gesting, urging, warning, and so on. Example: the speech act of prescribing that we
should respect our parents.
C. EXPRESSIVES: lamenting, regretting, apologizing, congratulating, greeting, thanking,
accepting, rejecting, objecting, cheering, and so on. Example: the speech act of
apologizing for having been rude.
D. COMMISSIVES: promising, adjourning, calling to order, bequeathing, baptizing,
guaranteeing, inviting, volunteering, naming, and so on. Example: the speech act
of naming one's cat 'Felix.'
Informatives are utterances aimed at reporting how things are. For example, a statement
that a thing has (or doesn't have) a quality ('Snow is white'); or that it is related to another thing
in a certain way ('Snow is softer than ice'). Directives are utterances aimed at eliciting an
audience's response, whether an answer (13) or an action (14).
13 How long is the line?
14 Pass me the salt!
Prohibitions are requests to refrain from doing something, so they qualify as directives-for
example,
1 5 No pets allowed.
As illustrated by (16), expressives are aimed at communicating a speaker's psychological world,
which includes attitudes (hopes, fears, desires, etc.) and feelings (of regret, thankfulness,
acceptance, rejection, exasperation, annoyance, etc.)
16 Good heavens!
Commissives convey the speaker's intent that the utterance itself bring about a state of affairs,
such as promising (17), adjourning, agreeing, and bequeathing.
17 At American Telecom, we guarantee you, our customers, unlimited free local calls.
BOX 4 ■ THE USES OF LANGUAGE
WHAT DO SPEAKERS
USE LANGUAGE FOR?
(A) REPRESENT THE FACTS
➔ INFORMATIVE$
(8) GET THE AUDIENCE TO
DO SOMETHING
➔ DIRECTIVES
(C) CONVEY THEIR OWN ATTITUDE
TOWARD AN AUDIENCE OR EVENT
➔ EXPRESSIVES
(D) COMMIT THEMSELVES TO AN
ACTION OR ATTITUDE ➔COMMISSIVES
IN QUESTIONS, THE
SPEAKER'S INTENTION
IS ELICITING AN ANSWER
IN REQUESTS, THE
SPEAKER'S INTENTION
IS ELICITING AN ACTION
Utterances can bring about such states of affairs, provided, of course, that some conditions are
met: for my words to count as bequeathing you my Ferrari, I must, to begin with, own a
Ferrari!
Finally, note that only informative expressions ('Snow is white') have straightforward truth
conditions: they are true if things are as represented by them and false otherwise. For the most
part, expressions of the other types don't have truth conditions, though they do have more
idiosyncratic conditions that must be met if the expressions are to succeed. The bottom line:
as illustrated by examples (13) through (17), it makes no sense to say that directives, expressives,
or commissives are true (or false).
Types of Sentence
A sentence falls under one or another of four types depending on its grammatical form. Natural
languages allow for constructing sentences of many different grammatical forms, which could
be grouped into the basic types listed in Box s below.
Sentences in the indicative mood are declarative ('Snow is white'). Although these sentences
are the primary vehicle for the informative use of language, they are sometimes the means for
directives ('Passengers are advised not to leave their luggage unattended'), commissives (17 above),
and even expressives ('I hope the rope is strong enough'). Imperative sentences are the principal
means for requests (15 above) and wishes ('Have fun'); interrogative sentences for questions
(13 above); and exclamatory sentences for expressives (16 above). The latter sentences can be used,
however, for emphatic requests (14) and assertions ('The king is dead!'). Some sentence types
relate better to certain uses of language, even when, except for interrogative sentences, there are
no one-to-one relations. Here is a summary of their relations:
w
0
<1'.
�
0
z
<1'.
_J
0
l-
o
z
�
�
0
a:
LL
C?
N
0
z
::<'.
i=
<(
a:
🙂
C)
LL
0
<(
w
cc
LL
<(
w
0
WW
cc 0
0�
�0
'
<( CJ
z
.. <( z _J
Q a:
I:: <(
zw
- _J
LL 0
Wz 0 :::>
L{) 0
N I-
DI
CJ
z
Q
<( w
CL
(j)
0
z
<(
�
_J
CJ
Oo
_J z CJ -
z�
Q (j)
z w
:i:Z
I- 0
Parallel between statements and beliefs: when speakers are sincere and the circumstances are
normal, their statements express their beliefs.
Propositions: the contents of statements and beliefs. Since each proposition is either true or
false, each statement is either true or false.
Direct links between sentence types and uses of language:
Sentence Types
DECLARATIVE
EXCLAMATORY
Speech Acts
IN FORMATIVES
DIRECTIVES
EXPRESSIVES
COM MISSIVES
Speech acts: The things we do simply by using language (informing, apologizing, greeting,
objecting, promising, recommending, etc.). There are four types of speech acts:
Informatives (language used to convey information)
Directives (language used to get the audience to do something)
Expressives (language used to express the speaker's psychological states)
Commissives (language used to bring about a state of affairs)
Figurative meaning: when an expression isn't used with its customary meaning, as in
metaphor and irony.
Definition: the standard means to clarify or revise the meaning of an expression. It has two
sides: what is to be defined (definiendum), and what does the defining (definiens). There are
three types of meaning definition:
Reportive definition: its definiens is synonymous with its definiendum. It's tested by
counterexample.
Ostensive definition: its definiens points to cases to which the definiendum applies.
Contextual definition: its definiens offers a replacement of the definiendum.
■ Key Words
Evidence
Truth conditions
Proposition
Declarative sentence
Speech act
Indirect speech act
Figurative language
Reportive definition
Ostensive definition
Contextual definition
The Virtues
of Belief
CHAPTER
This chapter looks more closely at beliefs, the building blocks of inference. In
connection with this, you'll learn about such topics as
Belief, disbelief, and nonbelief.
Some virtues of belief that are to be cultivated: accuracy, truth, reasonableness,
consistency, conservatism, and revisability.
■ Some vices of belief that are to be avoided: inaccuracy, falsity, unreasonableness,
inconsistency, dogmatism, and relativism.
The difference between empirical belief and conceptual belief.
The notions of self-contradiction, contradiction, and logically possible world.
■ The "supervirtue" of rationality and the "supervice" of irrationality.
49
LL
lJ.J
...J
lJ.J
ro
LL
0
U)
lJ.J
::)
I
II
>
lJ.J
I
I-
3.1 Belief, Disbelief, and Non belief
Beliefs and disbeliefs are two types of psychological attitudes people may have when they are
engaged in accepting what they think is true and rejecting what’s false. We’ll call these was states of
mind ‘cognitive attitudes’ (from the Latin, ‘cognoscere,’ which means ‘to know’). Nonbeliefs
represent the lack of either of these two attitudes. A belief is the cognitive attitude of accepting
a proposition, which is an information content representing states of affairs. Consider, for
example, the proposition expressed by
1 Dogs are carnivorous.
Anyone who believes (1) has the psychological attitude of accepting that dogs are carnivorous.
That person takes (1) to be true. If asked whether (1) is true, under normal circumstances, she
would assent. Assuming she’s sincere and competent, she could voice her belief by stating (1),
or many other sentences such as
2 It is true that dogs are carnivorous.
3 It is the case that dogs are carnivorous.
(1), (2), and (3) may be used to express the same content: namely, the proposition that dogs are
carnivorous.
Supposing we use ‘S’ to stand for a speaker ( or person), ‘P’ for a proposition, and ‘believing
that P’ for the psychological attitude of accepting that P, we can define belief in this way:
BOX 1 ■ BELIEF
S has a belief that P just in case S accepts that P. Assuming that the circumstances are normal and
S is sincere, if asked,
■ ‘Is P true ?’ S would assent.
■ ‘What do you make of P?’ S would assert sentences such as ‘P,’ ‘Pis true,’ and ‘It is the case that P.’
Note that the definition of belief in Box 1 invokes normal circumstances and the speaker’s
sincerity. In their absence, it may be that what a person S says is not what she believes. Because
there are deceivers (whose words misrepresent the beliefs they actually have) and self
deceivers (who deny the beliefs they actually have), we must assume the speaker’s sincerity
when we draw a parallel between what she says and what she believes. And because S might,
out of coercion, delusion, or other impairment, say something she doesn’t in fact believe, we
must assume normal circumstances, which include the speaker’s being competent-that is,
not mentally compromised, threatened, or impaired in any way.
But what about those who simply don’t believe a certain proposition, such as (1) above?
They may have either a disbelief or a nonbelief. A disbelief about (1) may be expressed by
sentences such as (4) through (6):
4 Dogs are not carnivorous.
5 It is false that dogs are carnivorous.
6 It is not the case that dogs are carnivorous.
Under normal circumstances, a person who sincerely says any of these disbelieves (1), which
amounts to having the psychological attitude of rejecting (1). If asked whether (1) is true, she
would dissent. And to voice her disbelief, she would deny (1}-for example, by asserting (4). We
may now summarize the concept of disbelief in this way:
BOX 2 ■ DISBELIEF
S has a disbelief that P just in case S rejects that P. Assuming that the circumstances are normal
and S is sincere, if asked,
■ ‘Is P true ?’ S would dissent.
■ ‘What do you make of P?’ S would deny that Pis true by uttering sentences such as ‘Pis false,’
‘Not P,’ and ‘It is not the case that P.’
What about those who neither believe nor disbelieve (1)? They have the attitude of
nonbelief about (1). Under normal circumstances, they would neither accept nor reject it. If
asked whether that content is true, they might shrug, giving no sign of assent or dissent. Box 3
summarizes all these reactions.
BOX 3 ■ NONBELIEF
S has a nonbelief that P just in case S neither accepts, nor rejects, that P. Assuming that the
circumstances are normal and S is sincere, if asked
■ ‘Is P true ?’ S would neither assent nor dissent.
■ ‘What do you make of P?’S would suspend judgment.
Nonbelieving that P, then, amounts to lacking any belief or disbelief about P. The corre
sponding psychological attitude is that of suspendingjudgment about P. We should bear in mind
that whenever we are considering whether to accept or reject a proposition-for example, that
dogs are carnivorous-there is also the option of nonbelief, which amounts to withholding
belief about a proposition. Thinking logically can help in developing the most adequate attitude
toward a proposition, whether that be accepting it, rejecting it, or suspending judgment about
it. Deciding which is the correct attitude matters, since our beliefs are the building blocks of our
reasoning. Here the rule is that, to keep the whole edifice sound, one must use high-quality
building blocks and do regular maintenance. But how are we to tell which building blocks of
reasoning are high-quality and which aren’t? That’s the topic of our next section.
BOX 4 ■ SECTION SUMMARY
Considering that P?
HERE ARE YOUR OPTIONS
BELIEF:
Accept that P
DISBELIEF: Reject
thatP
N0NBELIEF:
‘—–l Suspend judgment
aboutP
LL
w
_J
w
(l)
z
0
z
0
z
<(
LL
w
_J
w
(l)
U)
0
LL
w
_J
w
(l)
u..
w
....J
w
CD
u..
0
Exercises
1 . What is a belief? And what do we call the content of a belief?
2. What is the difference between a disbelief and a nonbelief?
3. Is nonbelief a kind of belief? If yes, why? If not, why not?
4. Think of two scenarios of your own where a person has a nonbelief.
5. Is disbelief a kind of belief? If yes, why? If not, why not?
6. In what does suspending judgment consist?
7. Why must the thinker's sincerity be assumed in order to take her statements to express her beliefs?
8. Why must the thinker's competence be assumed in order to take her statements to express her
beliefs?
� II. For each of the following, indicate whether it expresses a belief, a disbelief,
� or a nonbelief.
w
I
I-
1 . I accept that the Earth revolves.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Belief
2. I reject that the Pope is in Rome.
*3. I neither accept nor reject that God exists.
4. I think that it is false that cats are feline.
*5. In my opinion, it is the case that Newton was smart.
6. I'm convinced that it is not the case that the Moon is bigger than the Earth.
*7. I suspend judgment about whether there is life after death.
8. I neither accept nor reject the belief that there are UFOs.
*9. I'm sure that Barack Obama is tall.
10. In my view, no zealots can be trusted.
Ill. Report the belief, disbelief, or nonbelief expressed by each of the statements
below. Avoid reporting a disbelief as a belief with a negation inside the that-clause.
1 . The Earth is not a star.
SAMPLE ANSWER: The disbelief that the Earth is a star. [Avoid reporting this as "the belief that the Earth is
not a star."]
2. It is not the case that the Earth is not a planet.
3. It is false that Earth is a star.
*4. It is neither true nor false that the Sun will rise tomorrow.
5. Either the Earth is a star or it isn't.
*6. The Earth is a planet.
7. It is not the case that the Earth is a planet.
*8. It is neither true nor false that galaxies are flying outward.
9. Triangles are not figures.
*10. I am thinking.
11. I am not thinking.
*12. Is there life after death? I cannot say.
13. UFOs do not exist.
*14. I'm agnostic about whether humans are the product of evolution or divine creation.
15. If Pluto orbits the Sun, then it is a planet.
IV. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
*1. Explain why normal circumstances are a needed assumption in exercises (II) and (Ill) above.
2. Provide two examples of belief.
3. Recast your examples as examples of disbelief.
4. Provide two examples of nonbeliefs.
5. Recast your examples of nonbelief as examples of belief.
*6. Suppose you were considering the proposition that there is life after death. What cognitive attitudes
are your options? Report those attitudes.
3.2 Beliefs' Virtues and Vices
Among the traits or features of beliefs, some contribute to good reasoning and others to bad.
We may think of the good-making features as virtues, and of the bad-making ones as vices.
Prominent among the former is the supervirtue of rationality, and among the latter, the
supervice of irrationality. Why are these so significant? Because rationality marks the limits of
acceptable reasoning. Irrational beliefs are beyond that limit. In their case, the aims of
reasoning are, as we'll see, no longer achievable. In this section, we take up some virtues and
vices of belief, leaving rationality and irrationality for the next section. The features of beliefs
in our agenda now are those listed in Box 5.
BOX 5 ■ BELIEF'S VIRTUES AND VICES
Virtues
Accuracy
Truth
Reasonableness
Consistency
Conservatism
Revisability
Vices
Inaccuracy
Falsity
Unreasonableness
Inconsistency
Dogmatism
Relativism
(/)
w
0
>
0
z
(/)
LL
w
_J
w
al
N
(‘J
1111
LL
w
_J
w
Cl)
LL
0
(/)
w
🙂
f
a:
>
w
I
f-
First, note that since logical thinkers wish to avoid beliefs with bad-making features,
someone might think that it is advisable to avoid beliefs altogether. For if we didn’t have any
beliefs at all, we wouldn’t have any beliefs with bad-making features! But this advice is self
defeating, for it is not possible to avoid having beliefs. The very claim that logical thinkers are
better off without beliefs itself expresses a belief, assuming that those who make it are sincere
and competent. As logical thinkers, we must have some beliefs, so our aim should be simply to
have as many beliefs with good-making features, and as few with bad-making features, as
possible. Our aim, in other words, is that of maximizing the virtues and minimizing the vices
of beliefs. To say that a belief has a virtue is to praise it-while to say it has a vice is to criticize
it. Let’s now take up each of the virtues and vices of beliefs.
3.3 Accuracy and Truth
Accuracy and Inaccuracy
To have an acceptable degree of accuracy, a belief must either represent, or get close to
representing, the facts. In the former case, the belief is true-in the latter, merely approxi
mately true or close to being true. The following belief represents things as they actually are,
and it is therefore true:
7 Brasilia is the capital of Brazil.
True beliefs have the highest degree of accuracy. On the other hand, false beliefs have the high
est degree of inaccuracy, simply because they neither represent, nor get close to representing,
things as they actually are. For example,
8 Rio is the capital of Brazil.
Any belief that denies (8), which is false, would be true. Thus, that Rio is not the capital of
Brazil, and that it is not the case that Rio is the capital of Brazil, are both true-and therefore
have maximal accuracy. To determine this, we use the rule in Box 6.
Truth and Falsity
As logical thinkers, we should believe what is true and disbelieve what is false. But it is often dif
ficult to tell which beliefs are true and which are false. Thus sometimes we end up mistakenly
believing what is false-as when people in the Middle Ages believed that
9 The Sun revolves around the Earth.
They were, of course, later shown to be mistaken: (9) was always false, and therefore inaccurate.
For (9) not only fails to represent the facts truly, but (most crucially) never even got close at all to
When a belief is true, it has maximal accuracy; and when it is false, it has maximal inaccuracy.
representing them as they are. A belief can be more or less accurate depending on how close it is
to representing the facts as they are-that is, to getting them right. But some beliefs could be
accurate without being true. For example,
1 0 France is hexagonal.
11 Lord Raglan won the Battle of Alma. 1
(10) is roughly accurate, but not accurate enough to count as strictly true (not good enough
for a cartographer!). Similarly, (11) is accurate, but should we say it’s true? Well, it’s approxi
mately true. In fact, the battle was won by the British army, not just by its commander. Yet
it’s not clearly wrong to say that “Lord Raglan won it.” These examples suggest that accuracy
and inaccuracy are a matter of degree: some beliefs are closer to (or father from) repre
senting the facts than others are. Some beliefs are thus more accurate (or inaccurate) than
others. Yet truth and falsity are not a matter of degree at all: each belief is either true or false.
It makes no sense to say of a belief that it is ‘more true’ or ‘less true’ ( or ‘false’) than another
belief. A belief is either true or it isn’t. At the same time, both accuracy and truth are virtues
that either a single belief or a set of beliefs may have (likewise for the vices of inaccuracy and
falsity).
In the case of (12) and other beliefs that are vague, it is unclear whether they are true or
false, and also unclear whether they are accurate or inaccurate.
12 Queen Latifah is young.
Caution is likewise needed for statements that express evaluations such as (13). It is
controversial among philosophers whether evaluative statements are capable of being true or
false. Some such statements seem plainly true (“Hitler was evil”), others less clearly true than
BOX 7 ■ TRUTH AND ACCURACY
ACCURATE BELIEF
TRUE
BELIEF THAT
IS EITHER
(It corresponds
to the facts)
CLOSE TO
BEING TRUE
‘For more on puzzling examples of this sort, see J. L. Austin, ‘Performative-Constatif’ (La Philosophie Ana{ytique, Cahiers de
Royaumont, 1962).
I
f
::)
cr:
f-
0
z
<(
>–
0
<(
cr:
::)
0
0
<(
"'.
C')
LI..
LU
__J
LU
co
LI..
0
(/)
LU
=>
l
a:
>
LU
I
I-
11111
expressive of endorsement or attitudes of approval (“Frank Sinatra’s music is great”). Likewise
in judgments of taste such as
13 Ford Mustangs are better looking than Chevrolet Corvettes.
In cases of this sort, we’ll adopt the convention of simply indicating that they are statements of
value (more on this in Chapter 4).
3.4 Reasonableness
Beliefs that may fall short of being true, and even accurate, could still be reasonable. How is
this possible? To answer that question, let us consider the virtue of reasonableness and the vice
of unreasonableness, which, like accuracy and inaccuracy, are features that either a single
belief or a set of beliefs can have, and which come in degrees: some beliefs are more reason
able (or unreasonable) than others. Their, degree of reasonableness depends on how much
support of the adequate type they possess.
A belief is reasonable if and only if it has adequate support. Otherwise, it is unreasonable.
Beliefs of different types are supported in different ways. Thus how a belief might attain
reasonableness would vary according to its type. Since we’ll consider here only two kinds of
beliefs, empirical and conceptual, we’ll abstain, for the time being, from judging the
reasonableness of other types of beliefs: for example, of beliefs that are value judgments such
as (13) above.
Two Kinds of Reasonableness
What’s required for a belief to be reasonable varies according to what sort of belief it is.
Consider
14 Fido is barking.
15 Dogs bark.
(14) and (15) can be supported only by observation and are therefore empirical beliefs
(’empirical’ means observational). The kind of support needed for beliefs of this sort to be
reasonable differs from that of nonobservational beliefs. Among the latter are conceptual
beliefs, which may be supported by reasoning alone. For example,
167+5=12
17 A brother is a male sibling.
The grounds for (16) and (17) are conceptual: it is sufficient to understand the concepts
involved to realize that each of these beliefs is true. The truth of (16) is clear to anyone who
has mastered the numbers and the concept of addition-as is the truth of (17) to anyone
who has mastered the concepts, ‘brother’ and ‘male sibling.’ Thus (16) and (17) are both
reasonable, since each is supported by adequate reasoning alone.
A conceptual belief is reasonable if and only if all that’s needed to realize that the belief is
true is to master the concepts involved.
A reasonable conceptual belief, then, is one whose truth goes without saying once we
understand the content of the belief.
By contrast, (14) and (15) are not eligible for this kind of support: they require the support
of observation or evidence. In which circumstances would (14) or (15) be unreasonable?
Suppose that someone believes falsely that her dog, Fido, is barking now. That is, she believes
(14) even though she knows that Fido has been mute for many years. When challenged, she
engages in what is plainly a case of wishful thinking: her desire that Fido could bark somehow
makes her believe that the dog is barking. In this scenario, (14) would be unreasonable, simply
because it’s an empirical belief and the rule is
To be reasonable, empirical, beliefs must be supported either by evidence or by inference
from evidence.
As we saw in Chapter 2, evidence is the outcome of observation, which is provided by the
sensory experiences of seeing, hearing, touching, tasting, and/or smelling. Thus if as a result of
seeing Fido’s barking behavior and hearing him barking one comes to believe (14), then that
sensory experience itself would count as evidence for (14), thus rendering it reasonable to
believe (in the absence of evidence to the contrary). Trustworthy testimony also counts as
evidence, since we may consider it vicarious observation. Being supported by the evidence,
then, is all that’s usually needed for a belief like (14) to be reasonable.
On the other hand, for beliefs such as (15) to be reasonable, inference from evidence is
required. After all, (15) amounts to
15′ All dogs bark.
This belief is supported by the evidence and by other beliefs based on the available evidence.
The evidence consists in the observation that many dogs bark, from which one can infer that
all dogs bark. That is, one would need more than simply the firsthand evidence from
observing some barking dogs to support (15 1). After all, it is impossible to observe all barking
dogs. What else, apart from evidence, is contributing to its support? Other beliefs are
required, such as
18 A great number of dogs have been observed.
19 They all barked.
Cf)
Cf)
UJ
z
UJ
___J
CD
<(
z
0
Cf)
<(
UJ
er:
s:i:
C')
LI..
UJ
....J
UJ
co
LI..
0
(/)
UJ
:J
f
a:
>
UJ
I
f—
1111D
BOX 8 ■ TWO KINDS OF REASONABLE BELIEF
Supported by
Empirical evidence
Belief
Supported by
Two KINDS OF inference from
REASONABLE BELIEF evidence
Conceptual Supported by
Belief reasoning alone
On the basis of (18) and (19), it is reasonable to think that dogs bark. But if (15) is supported by
(18) and (19), then the relation among these is that of inference: (15) is inferred from (18)
and (19).
For empirical beliefs, then, evidence and inference from evidence are the two standard
routes to reasonableness. For conceptual beliefs, the route is reasoning alone. Empirical and
conceptual beliefs that lack the adequate kind of support would suffer from a substantial
degree of unreasonableness. Yet keep in mind that, for beliefs of other types, the criteria of
reasonableness may be different.
3.5 Consistency
Accuracy, truth, and reasonableness are virtues a single belief may have. Consistency, on the
other hand, is a virtue that on!}, a set of beliefs, two or more of them, can have-and likewise
for the vice of inconsistency. But what does ‘consistency’ mean?
Defining ‘Consistency’ and ‘Inconsistency’
A good place to start for a definition of ‘consistency’ is ‘inconsistency,’ since a set of beliefs is
consistent just in case it is not inconsistent. So, let’s begin with ‘inconsistency,’ defined thus:
A set of beliefs is inconsistent if and only if its members could not all be true at once.
Consider (20) and (21),
20 Dorothy Maloney is a senator.
21 Dorothy Maloney is a jogger.
These could both be true at the same time: Dorothy Maloney could be both a senator and a
jogger. But suppose we add the belief that
22 Dorothy Maloney is not a public official.
(20), (21), and (22) make up an inconsistent set, since it is impossible for all its members to be
true at the same time: clearly, no one could be a senator while at the same time failing to be a
public official. We may now say that
A set of beliefs is consistent if and only if its members could all be true at once.
To say that some beliefs are consistent is to say that they are logically compatible. Compatible
beliefs need not in fact be true: it is sufficient that they could all be true at once. Beliefs that are
actually false could make up a perfectly consistent or compatible set if they could all be true in
some possible scenario.
Logically Possible Propositions
Consider, for example, a set made up of
23 Arnold Schwarzenegger is a medical doctor.
24 Pigs fly.
(23) and (24) could both be true at once in some logically possible scenario or world. Our world,
which we’ll call the ‘actual world,’ is just one among many worlds that are logically possible
where a world is logically possible if it does not involve any contradiction. Logically impossible
worlds make no sense and are therefore unthinkable. We can also say that a proposition is
logically possible when it meets the condition in Box 9.
A proposition is logically possible if and only if it involves no contradiction.
Logically Impossible Propositions
Propositions that are not thinkable at all are logically impossible, necessarily false, or absurd, as
illustrated by each of the following:
25 All pigs are mammals, but some pigs are not mammals.
26 Arnold Schwarzenegger is a medical doctor and he isn’t.
27 Arnold Schwarzenegger is a married bachelor.
Propositions of this sort are self-contradictions.
>-
0
z
w
f
(/)
(/)
z
0
0
�
C’)
LL
LU
::i
LU
a)
LL
0
(j)
LU
🙂
f
a:
>
LU
I
f-
BOX 10 ■ SELF-CONTRADICTION
■ A proposition is self-contradictory if and only if it is necessarily false or logically impossible.
■ A self-contradictory proposition is false all by itself in every possible world, not just in the
actual world.
(25), (26), and (27) illustrate self-contradictions: each is logically impossible or necessarily false,
owing to its having self-contradictory concepts or logical words. A quick inspection of (25) and
(26) shows that there is no possible world in which either one could be true, simply because
they have, respectively, these logical forms:
25′ All such-and-such are so-and-so, but some such-and-such are not so-and-so.
26′ X has a certain feature and does not have it.
(25′) and (26′) exhibit arrangements of logical words (in italics) that make it impossible for any
proposition with either of these arrangements to be true. Each is therefore logically self-con
tradictory. On the other hand, (27) is conceptually self-contradictory: given the concepts
involved, there is no possible world where (27) could be true. No one could literally be a married
bachelor,just as no triangle could have four internal angles. Any proposition with such contents
would be absurd or nonsensical and therefore unthinkable, since it would be impossible to
comprehend its content.
It is not only individual propositions that could be logically impossible: entire sets of propo
sitions could be. That would be the case in any inconsistent set. Inconsistency occurs in either of
these two cases: the set has some propositions that are logically incompatible or contradictory
among themselves, or the set has at least one self-contradictory proposition. The propositions
that Dorothy Maloney is a senator and that she is not a public official illustrate the first case of
inconsistency, that of a set containing contradictory propositions. By the definitions of inconsis
tency and contradiction, any set consisting of contradictory propositions is inconsistent.
Any two propositions are contradictory just in case they cannot have the same truth
value: if one is true, the other must be false, and vice versa.
Consistency and Possible Worlds
Let’s now reconsider the following set:
23 Arnold Schwarzenegger is a medical doctor.
24 Pigs fly.
These propositions, though actually false, are nonetheless consistent. For there are possible
worlds (i.e., scenarios involving no contradiction) where they could be compatible. In those
possible worlds, they are both true at the same time: for example, a world where Arnold
Schwarzenegger never became a movie star but became a medical doctor instead, and where
pigs were anatomically equipped to overcome the force of gravity so that they could fly.
In light of these considerations, ‘consistent’ and ‘inconsistent’ may be recast as the following:
A set of beliefs is consistent if and only if
■ There is a logically possible world where its members could all be true at once.
A set of beliefs is inconsistent if and only if
■ There is no logically possible world where its members could be all true at once.
Consistency in Logical Thinking
Given the above definitions, no set of contradictory beliefs is eligible for consistency.
Inconsistency, or failure of consistency, amounts to a serious flaw, since it offends against our
intuitive sense of what is logically possible and, to that extent, thinkable at all. Inconsistent
beliefs are to be avoided completely. Whenever a set of beliefs is found to be inconsistent,
logical thinkers must first ask whether it can be made consistent, and if it can, then they must
take the necessary steps to make it so. How? By revising it in a way that eliminates the source
of inconsistency. Recall our inconsistent set:
20 Dorothy Maloney is a senator.
21 Dorothy Maloney is a jogger.
22 Dorothy Maloney is not a public official.
To remove the inconsistency here requires that either (20) or (22) be abandoned.
Note, however, that although consistency is a virtue, it is not a guide to accuracy or even to
reasonableness. Beliefs that could all be true in some possible scenario might, as we have seen,
in fact be false and even quite preposterous in our actual world. Another thing to notice is
that, like truth and falsity, neither consistency nor inconsistency comes in degrees. No set of
beliefs can be ‘sort of consistent’: it’s either consistent or inconsistent. We’ll now turn to con
servatism, a virtue of beliefs closely related to consistency.
BOX 11 ■ CONSISTENCY AND LOGICAL THINKING
A salient feature of logical thinkers is that they reflect upon their beliefs ( or the statements they
make) and try to make them consistent.
3.6 Conservatism and Revisability
Conservatism without Dogmatism
Conservatism or familiarity is a virtue that our beliefs have insofar as they are consistent with
other beliefs of ours. That is, beliefs have this virtue if they fit in with the beliefs we presently
have. Suppose that in a circus performance we observe that
28 A person inside a box was cut in two halves, later emerging unharmed.
>
I:::
co
<(
(I)
>
w
a:
0
z
<(
�
(I)
a:
w
(I)
z
0
0
(0
(")
LL.
LU
...J
LU
aJ
LL.
0
Cl)
LU
🙂
,-
>
LU
I
,-
Shall we accept (28)? Although (28) appears based on observational evidence, it’s inconsistent with
beliefs we already have, such as that
29 No one who has been cut in two halves could emerge unharmed.
Conservatism recommends that we reject (28) and that we take it to report nothing more than
a clever illusionist’s trick. The more outlandish a belief is, the less conservative it is.
Yet conservatism has to be balanced with revisability, to which we’ll turn below. Otherwise,
conservatism could lead to accepting only what is consistent with what we already believe,
whether the evidence supports it or not-which would be not only unreasonable, but dogmatic.
Dogmatism is the vice that some revisable beliefs have when they are held immune to
revision. Those who have beliefs with a significant share of this vice are dogmatists.
Dogmatism conflicts with revisability, a virtue that boils down to the open-mindedness needed
for the accuracy, reasonableness, and consistency of our beliefs. For our beliefs to have any of
these virtues, they must be revised often in light of new evidence and further reasoning.
Revisability without Extreme Relativism
Revisability is the virtue that beliefs have insofar as they are open to change. It comes in
degrees, as do accuracy and reasonableness. But, unlike them, revisability has an upper limit:
too much revisability may lead to extreme relativism, the vice of thinking that everything is a
matter of opinion. This makes sense only when beliefs are taken to be ‘true for’ a group of
people-rather than ‘true period.’ With the qualification ‘true for,’ the relativist can say that, for
example, the belief that the Earth doesn’t move was true for people in antiquity. At the same
time, it is not true for us. And there is no contradiction here.
Thus, given extreme relativism, some contradictory beliefs could all be equally true at the
same time. But this clashes with some common intuitions. One is that
A belief is true if and onry if it corresponds to the facts.
Plainly, it is false that the Earth didn’t move in antiquity. That belief did not correspond to
the facts then, just as it doesn’t correspond to the facts now. Moreover, given relativism, ‘true’
is actually ‘true for … ,’ where the dots could be filled in with ‘culture,’ ‘social group,’ ‘historical
period,’ or whatever is the preference of the relativists. This leads to the relativists’ acceptance
of at least some contradictions, since opposite beliefs may be ‘true for,’ for example, different
cultures. But a strong view in the West since antiquity is that contradiction makes dialogue
among logical thinkers impossible.
BOX 12 ■ CONSERVATISM VS. ACCURACY
Logical thinkers must not be too strict about conservatism, for sometimes beliefs that seem not to
be conservative turn out to be accurate-or even true!
How much revisability, then, counts as a virtue? In fact, this varies according to belief type.
Consider mathematical and logical beliefs such as
30 6 is the square root of 36.
31 Either Lincoln is dead or he isn’t.
These may perhaps be counted as needing very little of that virtue at all. And similarly for
32 Lawyers are attorneys.
Other beliefs of these types, which are all supported by reasoning alone, may also be only mar
ginally revisable. They will typically have the highest degree of conservatism and the lowest de
gree of revisability.
On the other hand, consider empirical and memory beliefs such as
33 The John Hancock Building is Chicago’s tallest building.
34 I visited the John Hancock Building in 1996.
These have a great share of revisability. (33), an empirical belief, can be revised in light
of evidence (it is in fact false), as can (34), which could be nothing more than a false
memory. Beliefs of either type change in light of evidence, provided that they are not
held dogmatically.
If we allow our beliefs to be changed too easily and too frequently, we may end up thinking
that contradictory beliefs could all be true at once-or that ‘true’ just means ‘true for.’ This
is the vice of extreme relativism.
3. 7 Rationality vs. Irrationality
Rationality is the supervirtue characteristic of all beliefs within the limits of reasoning, while
irrationality is the supervice characteristic of all beliefs beyond that limit. Although a person’s
actions may also be said to be rational in some cases and irrational in others, here we shall
consider these features only insofar as they apply to beliefs. Rational belief requires the condi
tions listed here.
Condition (1) limits the range of beliefs to which (2) and (3) apply: not all beliefs,
but just the beliefs a thinker is presently and consciously considering. Typically, as thinkers
BOX 13 ■ RATIONAL BELIEF
A thinker’s belief is rational only if the thinker
1. Has it presently and consciously in his mind,
2. Could provide evidence or reasons for it, and
3. Is not aware of the belief’s failing any of the virtues discussed above.
>
I-
….J
<(
z
0
0:
0:
(j)
>
>
I
___J
<(
z
0
I
<(
0:
,.__
C')
LL
w
_J
w
m
0
(/)
w
::J
f
a:
w
I
f-
-
we have many beliefs, but only some of them are the focus of conscious attention at any
given time. Since the vast majority of them are, so to speak, in the back of our minds,
then given condition (1), those beliefs can be neither rational nor irrational. Current
conscious beliefs, on the other hand, must be either rational or irrational, depending on
whether or not they satisfy conditions (2) and (3). Given (2), the rationality of beliefs requires
that the thinker be able to account for them. Given (3), rationality requires that the thinker
not be aware of her beliefs' failing in accuracy, truth, reasonableness, consistency, conser
vatism, and/or revisability. Suppose a thinker is currently, consciously entertaining these
beliefs:
35 My neighbor Sally Chang died and was resuscitated.
36 No person can die and be resuscitated.
37 (35) and (36) are not consistent.
We may further suppose that the thinker is not only aware of her beliefs' lack of consistency,
but does nothing to revise them to restore consistency. Thus her beliefs are irrational.
Similarly, they would be irrational if, once challenged, the thinker could produce no reason
whatsoever for having those beliefs. Derivatively, the thinker herself may in both cases be said
to be irrational.
BOX 14 ■ RATIONAL VS IRRATIONAL BELIEF
THE THINKER
CAN PROVIDE
A REASON FOR
HAVING THEM
n f RATIONAL
THE THINKER IS
NOT
AWARE OF ANY
VICES
CONSCIOUS, IN THEM
CURRENTLY HELD
BELIEFS EITHER OR
THE THINKER THE THINKER
CANNOT PROVIDE - ls AWARE OF
A REASON FOR VICES
1
I
HAVING THEM IN THEM
IRRATIONAL
I
OR
BOTH
Exercises
1 . When is a belief accurate? How is truth related to accuracy?
2. Why does belief type matter for reasonableness?
3. Does consistency come in degrees? Explain.
4. When are beliefs consistent? How is consistency related to truth and possible worlds?
5. When is a belief revisable? How is revisability related to conservatism?
6. What is dogmatism? Give a reason why it should be avoided.
7. What is relativism? Give a reason why it should be avoided.
8. How does the relativist understand truth?
VI. Some of the following statements qualify as accurate or inaccurate. Others are
vague or evaluative. Indicate which is which.
1. David Copperfield is Dickens's finest novel.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Evaluative statement
2. 1,000 grains of sand make up a heap.
*3. New York City is the capital of the United States.
4. New York City is located in the state of New York.
*5. A five-foot-ten person is tall.
6. To be a dog is to be a reptile.
*7. Hip-hop is better than jazz.
8. Everybody likes Picasso's paintings.
9. Killing animals for food is wrong.
*10. Wikileaks published secret government documents.
11 . The Vikings were the first Europeans to visit North America.
12. All members of the Texas legislature are space aliens from another galaxy.
*13. High blood pressure is a dangerous medical condition.
14. The Amazon River is located in Russia.
*15. Slavery is unjust.
VII. Determine which of the statements listed in (VI) above are empirical and which
aren't (answers to 3, 5, 7, 10, 13, and 15 in the back of the book).
1. David Copperfield is Dickens's finest novel.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Not an empirical statement
>–
1-
_J
>-
1-
_J
I
_J
<(
z
0
er:
er:
(j)
>
>
t::
_J
<(
z
0
I
<(
er:
LL
w
_j
w
CD
LL
0
(/)
w
::J
f
a:
w
I
f-
*7. Whales are fish.
8. The Earth is flat.
*9. Chickens can't fly long distances.
10. The lines of your palm contain information about your future.
*11. There are no witches.
12. Water is H2O.
*13. Sarah Palin is a Democrat.
14. Alabama is a southern state.
*15. There are out-of-body experiences.
XII. Determine whether the following combinations of propositions are rational or
irrational:
1. I know that a bachelor can't be married. Yet I'm a married bachelor.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Irrational
2. I'm aware that Jane was childless in 1989, but now she has four grandchildren!
*3. I do believe that elephants are extinct and that they aren't extinct.
4. In my view, God does not exist-and neither do angels.
*5. Although there are no good reasons for believing that the end of the universe is coming, I believe it is.
6. I believe that all cats are felines and that some cats are not felines. Furthermore, I believe that these
beliefs are contradictory.
*7. As a zoologist, I have no doubts that cats are felines and that all felines are mammals. I'm not aware
of these beliefs being defective.
8. I have never seen muskrats. Moreover, I have never acquired any information whatsoever about
them. As far as I'm concerned, they are rodents.
*9. There is no evidence that there is an afterlife. Yet I prefer to believe that there is.
10. I believe that Mario and Lucille have a romantic relationship. Yes, Brian says that they do, but he is
not a reliable source of information about who is dating whom. But I learned about their relationship
from a trustworthy source.
XIII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1 . Give three examples of irrational belief.
2. Explain why your examples for (1) above are irrational. What would be required to make them rational?
3. Provide a scenario in which a thinker is a dogmatist.
4. Provide a scenario in which a thinker is a relativist.
5. Write three sets of inconsistent beliefs.
6. Protagoras of Abdera (Greek, c. 490-421 B.C.E.) argued that "man [i.e., human beings] is the meas
ure of all things-of things that are, that they are, and of things that are not, that they are not. As a
thing appears to a man, so it is." How does this amount to a relativist position? What sort of objections
might be brought against it?
■ Writing Project
Choose one of the following two projects and write a short composition:
1. A nonsense essay, where you describe three logically impossible scenarios, and then
explain why they are logically impossible.
2. Consider the passage below, from Lewis Carroll's Alice in Wonderland.
"I can't believe that!" said Alice.
"Can't you?" the Queen said in a pitying tone. "Try again: draw a long breath, and
shut your eyes."
Alice laughed. "There's no use trying," she said: "one can't believe impossible
things."
"I dare say you haven't had much practice," said the Queen. "When I was your age
I always did it for half-an-hour a day. Why, sometimes, I've believed as many as six
impossible things before breakfast."
Write a short essay where you explain Alice's refusal's to believe impossible things. You may
invoke the virtue of conservatism, explaining what it is and how it sometimes leads to refusing
to believe things that one "sees."
■ Chapter Summary
Belief: a psychological attitude of accepting a proposition.
Disbelief: a psychological attitude of rejecting a proposition.
Nonbelief: the lack of a psychological attitude of accepting or rejecting a proposition.
Virtue: a good-making trait.
Vice: a bad-making trait.
Accuracy: a belief's virtue of being either true or close to being true. Related vice: inaccuracy.
A matter of degree.
Truth: a belief's virtue of representing the facts as they are. Related vice: falsity. Not a matter of
degree.
Reasonableness: for an empirical belief, the virtue of being supported by evidence, or infer
ence from evidence; for a conceptual belief, that of being based on good reasons. Related vice:
unreasonableness. A matter of degree.
Consistency: virtue of a set of beliefs insofar as they could all be true at once. Related vice:
inconsistency. Not a matter of degree.
>
a:
<{
�
�
::>
(f)
a:
w
l
o..
<{
I
0
ml
LL
w
_J
w
(l)
LL
0
(J)
w
::J
f
a:
>
w
I
f-
Conservatism: a belief’s virtue of being compatible with other beliefs we already have. Related
vice: dogmatism. A matter of degree.
Revisability: a belief’s virtue of being held open to change. Related vice: extreme relativism.
A matter of degree.
Rationality: a supervirtue a belief has insofar as is currently and consciously held by the
thinker, who has some reason to support it and is not aware of the belief’s having any of the
listed vices. Related supervice: irrationality. When a belief is irrational, that’s a compelling
reason to reject it.
■ Key Words
Belief Contradiction
Disbelief Self-contradiction
Nonbelief Conservatism
Accuracy Dogmatism
Truth Extreme relativism
Reasonableness Revisability
Consistency Rationality
Part
Reason and Argument
CHAPTER
Tips for Argument
Analysis
This chapter considers some techniques for argument reconstruction. Here you’ll
learn about
The roles of faithfulness and charity in reconstructing arguments.
Arguments that have missing premises.
Recognizing extended arguments and their component parts.
The distinction between deduction and induction.
Normative reasoning
■ Normative arguments and missing normative premises.
73
1-
z
w
2
::i
0
0:
<(
0: (j)
o en
LL �
(j) <(
0.. z
� <(
IIEI
4.1 A Principled Way of Reconstructing Arguments
That we endorse a certain claim, or reject it, is never the primary aim of argument analysis.
Rather, its aim is to decide whether a certain claim should be accepted or rejected on the basis
of the premises (reasons) offered for it. But this requires that we first get clear about two
requirements of correct argument reconstruction. One is faithfolness, the other charity-that
point to the concerns listed in Box 1.
Faithfulness
Being faithful to the arguer's intention is crucial to argument reconstruction. To meet this
requirement, we must observe the principle of faithfulness in interpretation, which recom
mends that we strive to put ourselves in the shoes of the arguer. That is, we must try to repre
sent her argument exactly as she intends it. Failing that, we're not dealing with the actual
argument under discussion, but some other one we have made up!
Charity
Another crucial requirement of argument analysis is that we make the argument as strong as
possible. That is, we must observe a second principle, that of charity in interpretation, which
recommends that we reconstruct an argument in the way that maximizes the truth of its parts
and the strength of their logical relation. We must, in other words, try to give "the benefit of
the doubt" to the arguer, and take her argument to be as strong as possible. Maximizing truth
requires that we interpret an argument's premises and conclusion in a way so that they come
out true, or at least close to true. And maximizing the strength of an argument requires that we
interpret the relation of inference among its premises and conclusion in a way that is as strong
as possible. In an argument where that relation is strongest of all, if its premises are true, its
conclusion must also be. But, as we shall see, not all arguments can be interpreted as
consisting in a relation of that sort. For a summary of the two requirements for adequate
reconstruction of arguments, see Box 2.
BOX 1 ■ TWO CONCERNS IN ARGUMENT
RECONSTRUCTION
1. How to phrase the argument so that it captures the arguer's intentions.
2. How to phrase the argument so that it comes out as strong as possible.
When Faithfulness and Charity Conflict
Although faithfulness and charity are both indispensable to argument analysis and are in most
cases compatible, these two principles do, nevertheless, sometimes come into conflict. This
happens when maximizing the one implies minimizing the other. Let's consider some
examples, beginning with one where faithfulness and charity get along well. Someone argues
1 House rules do not allow dogs in the lobby, but dogs are there. So there has been a
breach of house rules.
BOX 2 ■ FAITHFULNESS AND CHARITY
In reconstructing an argument, keep in mind:
■ The principle of faithfulness
✓ It recommends that we try to set out as carefully as possible exactly what the arguer mean
to say.
■ The principle of charity
✓ It recommends that we take the argument seriously, giving it the benefit of the doubt and
maximizing the truth and logical connectedness of its parts.
The second premise may be recast as 'Dogs are in the lobby,' which could be interpreted
in two ways: it is either referring to (a) all members of the species dog or (b) just some mem
bers of that species. Which one should we choose? Charity and faithfulness both suggest that
we choose (b), since otherwise the premise would be false and also say something that doesn't
capture the arguer's intentions (and our interpretation would then fail on both charity and
faithfulness). Reconstructed without these shortcomings, (1) reads
2 1. House rules do not allow dogs in the lobby.
2. Some dogs are in the lobby.
3. There has been a breach of house rules.
Here charity and faithfulness don't clash. But let's consider an argument where the two princi
ples do seem to pull in opposite directions:
3 The following two reasons absolutely prove that witches do not exist: (1) there is no
evidence that they exist, and (2) to invoke witches doesn't really explain anything.
Here faithfulness pulls us toward interpreting this argument as one in which the conclusion is
supposed to follow with necessity from the premises. That's precisely what "absolutely prove"
amounts to. Under that interpretation, however, the argument fails: it is plainly false that its
conclusion follows necessarily from its premises, since the premises could be true (as in fact
they are in this case) and the conclusion false.
On the other hand, charity pulls us toward reading (3) as making the more modest claim
that its conclusion is a reasonable one on the basis of the argument's premises. Under this
interpretation, the argument may be recast as
3' The following two reasons make it likely that witches do not exist: (1) there is no
evidence that witches exist, and (2) to invoke witches doesn't really explain anything.
We have now maximized the argument's strength, since although (3')'s premises could be true
and its conclusion false, the former give good reasons for the latter: the conclusion is likely to
be true if the argument's premises are true. Instead of failing, (3') turns out to provide support
for its conclusion. But maximizing charity, in this case, comes at the price of minimizing faith
fulness: (3') simply isn't what the arguer seems to have had in mind in proposing (3)! Yet since
faithfulness always carries the greater weight, here we should stick to our first reading of (3),
which is the one that maximizes faithfulness.
Cl)
1-z
w
u.. �
0 ::J
>– 0
<{ a:
� <{
o
….J
(J)
f-
�
�
1-
z
w
�
::)
CJ
a:
I-
f
z
w
‘.:2
🙂
0
a:
<(
a: (/)
0 ui
LL >–
(/) <( e::z f- <( 17. Today I met someone in an Internet chat room. But there is no chance that we could have a suc cessful long-term relationship, for no people who meet in internet chat rooms can have successful long-term relationships. *18. Some Texans are tall. Billy Bob is a Texan. Therefore, Billy Bob is tall. 19. No sharks are friendly. Hammerheads are sharks. Therefore, no hammerheads are friendly. *20. Columbus was either Spanish or Italian. He was not Spanish. Therefore, he was Italian. 21. Lady Gaga has no problems. She is a famous singer, and no famous singer has problems. 22. All famous politicians are celebrities. Some governors are famous politicians; therefore, some gover nors are celebrities. *23. Some comedians are Canadians. Mike Meyers is a comedian. So Mike Meyers is probably a Canadian. 24. Lake Michigan most likely carries commercial shipping, since it's one of the Great Lakes, and the other Great Lakes carry commercial shipping. *25. No hip-hop artist is a fan of harmonica music. Since Zoltan is a fan of harmonica music, it follows that he is not a hip-hop artist. VIII. All the arguments below have missing premises and may be counted as either deductive or inductive, depending on what missing premises are put in. For each argument, provide the missing premise that would make it (a) deductive, or (b) inductive. Some flexibility in wording is allowed! 1. People waste a huge amount of time surfing the web. It follows that the web is not such a great invention. SAMPLE ANSWER: 1 a: No invention that allows people to waste a huge amount of time is great. 1 b: Many inventions that allow people to waste a huge amount of time are not great. 2. Ellen is a sophisticated artist, hence she listens to jazz. 3. Digsby was fired. After all, he had been spending all day surfing the web. 4. Latino purchasing power is approaching billions of dollars in the United States. Therefore, there will be better employment opportunities for talented Latinos. 5. Air Canada is an airline. Therefore, Air Canada charges a baggage fee to passengers who check bags. 6. The British red squirrel is a rodent. Consequently, the British red squirrel is an endangered species. 7. The galaxies are flying outward. This suggests that the Milky Way Galaxy will spin apart. 8. Mount Everest is a tall mountain. Therefore, Mount Everest is difficult to climb. 9. President Calvin Coolidge was a fiscal conservative. So he was not a gambler. 10. The NAFTA treaty regulates North American commercial relations. Therefore, the NAFTA treaty is unpopular with opponents of free trade. IX. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB 1. Consider the claim 'Ray has at least one sibling.' Write two arguments for it, one deductive (i.e., pro viding conclusive reasons) and the other inductive (i.e., providing nonconclusive reasons). 2. Write an argument with a missing premise, and then identify that premise. 3. Consider the claim 'There is life after death.' Write an argument for it and another one against it. Discuss whether these arguments are conclusive or nonconclusive. 4.5 Norm and Argument What Is a Normative Argument? We've seen that all arguments fall into either one of the other of two classes: they're either deductive or inductive. From a different perspective, both deductive and inductive arguments could be classified as being either normative or non-normative. The examples we've discussed in this book up to now have nearly all been made up entirely of statements that assert or deny some facts (or putative facts) about the world, such as 'Toronto is the largest city in Ontario,' 'Mercury is heavier than water,' and 'Jerry Seinfeld is a comedian.' Statements of this sort fall under the category of non-normative. But some other expressions go beyond facts to assess in dividuals, actions, and things, or to say what an individual ought to do (or ought not to do) or how things should be (or not be). For example, 'You ought to keep your promises,' 'Reggae music is cool,' 'Hitler was evil,' and 'Elena deserves credit for her hard work.' Expressions of this latter type are used to make normative judgments, which figure in a sort of reasoning that we'll call normative reasoning. When we make a normative judgment and offer reasons intended to support it, the result is a normative argument. These are arguments for the conclusion that something has a certain value, such as being good or bad, right or wrong, just or unjust, beautiful or ugly, and the like. Also, arguments for the conclusion that something is permissible (may be done), obligatory (ought to be done), or forbidden (should not �e done) may be classified as being normative arguments. Consider 14 1. One ought to obey one's parents. 2. My parents told me not to go to the party on Friday night. 3. I ought not to go the party on Friday night. The conclusion of (14) is a normative judgment, since it represents a certain action (going to the party on Friday night) as being forbidden. By doing so, it directs or guides the arguer's be havior in a certain way-namely, away from the Friday-night party. That the conclusion is a normative judgment here is sufficient to make argument (14) normative. In addition, (14)'s premise 1 belongs to the category of general normative judgments, sometimes also called 'principles,' because they state rules that are supposed to apply not just to one person, but to anyone. We may distinguish between normative judgments that express a generalization or rule and those-like (14)'s conclusion-that are particular sentences used to make claims about individual persons, things, events, and so on. The distinctions we have in mind here are summarized in Box 6. 1- z w :'? ::J (9 a: <( 0 z <( :'? a: 0 z "'. '3" ml 1- z w � :::, (.') a: <( a: Cf) 0 in LL >–
_j
Cf) <(
� z
I- <(
BOX 6 ■ NORMATIVE JUDGMENTS
NORMATIVE
JUDGEMENTS
OF OBLIGATION
OF VALUE
GENERAL
PARTICULAR
GENERAL
PARTICULAR
Judgments of obligation involve concepts such as right and wrong, and duty (what we're
obligated to do or forbear from doing, what we're permitted to do or forbidden to do). For
example,
15 You ought not to deceive your friends.
16 Spreading that malicious rumor about Anderson was wrong.
Judgments of value, or simply evaluative judgments, are about the value of actions or
things (whether they are good or bad, just or unjust, etc.). For example,
17 Honest people make good co-workers.
18 The desert of southern Utah is beautiful.
(15) and (17) are general: they purport to apply to a set of individuals or things. (16) and (18) are
particular: they purport to apply to a single individual or thing.
Of concern here are certain general and particular normative judgments about matters of
taste, the law, prudence, and morality. We'll classify them accordingly as aesthetic, legal,
prudential, or moral judgments. Whenever any such normative judgment is the conclusion of
an argument, we'll say that the argument itself is aesthetic, legal, prudential, or moral, as the
case may be. A normative judgment is aesthetic just in case it expresses an evaluation or norm
involving a matter of taste such as that some piece of art is beautiful or ugly, a dish is tasty or
inedible, or that we ought to admire good music. Aesthetic judgments could be either particu
lar ('Beyonce's recordings are superior art,' 'Frank Lloyd Wright's designs are overrated,' 'The
Parliament buildings in Ottawa are a majestic sight') or general ('White socks don't go well
with black shoes,' 'You ought to watch Law and Order').
The conclusion of a legal argument features a normative judgment involving a legal mat
ter: something that's said to be a duty or obligation according to the law, or to be permitted to
do or forbidden to do by statute-for example, that drivers ought not to tear up a parking ticket
or are permitted to turn right on red (except in New York City!) and that adults have a duty to
file an income tax return. Legal normative judgments could have a conditional form, as in 'If a
person is called for jury service, that person must show up,' and 'When a person is sworn as a
witness in court, that person is obligated to tell the truth.'
The conclusion of a prudential argument makes a claim about what it would be in your
own self-interest to do, such as 'You ought to be especially nice to your rich Aunt Gertrude,' 'It's
not in your interest to antagonize your boss,' 'People should look out for themselves first!' and
'Don't cheat your business associates if you don't want them to cheat you.'
The conclusion of a moral argument is a moral judgment. Judgments of this sort make a
claim about what is good or bad, just or unjust, and what ought (or ought not) to be done, not
because it's sanctioned by the law, but because, as the case may be, it deserves praise or
blame- for example, 'Lying is wrong,' 'You ought to help the earthquake survivors,' 'Matthew's
behavior was dishonest,' and 'The firefighters showed great courage on 9/11.'
The upshot, then, is that when normative judgments of any of these four types occur in
the conclusion of an argument, the argument is itself normative. And it's by paying attention
to the type of normative judgment in the conclusion that we tell which type of normative
argument it is: aesthetic, legal, prudential, or moral.
Missing Normative Premises
Earlier in this chapter, we saw that when arguments are presented in everyday language,
they sometimes have missing premises that need to be restored if the argument is to be
reconstructed in a way that respects the principles of faithfulness and charity. One especially
common way in which important premises may be left out is a pattern that sometimes
occurs in normative arguments. In fact, such arguments often have normative judgments,
not only in their conclusions, but also in at least one premise, and it's that premise that is
sometimes left out.
What we shall call normative general premises, such as 'Keeping promises is right,' 'Slavery
is unjust,' or 'One ought to obey the law,' are judgments that may seem to the arguer too obvi
ous to need repeating, and so they may get left out. Here are some examples of normative ar
guments in which the normative general premises are in place. As you read them, try imagin
ing what they'd sound like with that crucial premise left out.
19 Legal argument:
1. Driving faster than 55 miles per hour on the Taconic Parkway
is forbidden by law. � NORMATIVE GENERAL PREMISE
2. Yesterday I drove faster than 55 miles per hour on the Taconic Parkway.
3. Yesterday I did what I ought not to do, according to the law.
20 Aesthetic argument:
1. Music that consists of only a random collection of honks, bleats,
and screeches is worthless noise. � NORMATIVE GENERAL PREMISE
2. Professor Murgatroyd's 'Second Symphony' consists of only a random collection
of honks, bleats, and screeches.
3. Professor Murgatroyd's 'Second Symphony' is worthless noise.
r
z
w
2
::J
(9
a:
<
0
z
<
2
a:
0
z
"'.
s;-
DIii
1-
z w
2
::)
CJ a:
–
…J
(./)
0
a::
<(
a:: (/)
0 U)
LL :'.:j
(/) <(
0. z
i= <(
5. Mendoza & Co. are honest brokers. After all, their dealings with me have always been fair.
*6. On the R train, it would take you twenty minutes to travel the same distance that now takes you forty
minutes on the local bus. Thus you are better off taking the R train.
7. That witness is committing perjury. Therefore, he should be prosecuted.
8. Cookies are full of sugar. As a result, they are not good for you.
*9. Sandy deals poorly with her financial problems. Thus she ought to get married.
10. Having a college degree will improve your earning potential, so you should finish your degree.
11. Spreading false rumors about one's competitors is a form of lying; therefore, spreading false rumors
about one's competitors is wrong.
*12. Celine Dion's songs are the best. After all, her songs are always hits.
13. Since the ocean is rough today, swimming is not a smart idea.
14. SUVs pollute the atmosphere worse than cars, so they are bad for the health of Americans.
*15. Jason ought to report for active duty in Afghanistan. After all, Jason is a member of the Army Reserve,
and his commanding officer ordered all the soldiers in his unit to report for active duty in Afghanistan.
16. Since The Jerry Gordon Show is watched by millions, it follows that it's great television.
17. Everybody knows that Frank betrayed his friends, so Frank is a reprehensible character.
*18. Capital punishment is the appropriate punishment for murder. Therefore, capital punishment is
ethically justified.
19. A former president is a big fan of Raymond Chandler's novels. So Raymond Chandler's novels are
great literature.
*20. You ought to pay that traffic ticket right away. After all, that's the law.
XIV. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. Write an argument with a missing normative premise, and then identify the type of normative
sentence that it exemplifies.
2. Suppose you're in the checkout line at the supermarket. The cashier asks you, "Paper or plastic?"
What sort of normative reasons could be relevant in answering this question? Discuss.
3. Oskar Schindler was a German industrialist in the 1940s and a member of the Nazi Party, but he
helped many Jews escape the death camps. Now, clearly Schindler was disloyal to his superiors.
But do we want to say he behaved badly? We don't want to say that! Can you see what the problem
is here? What kind of word is 'disloyal'? Write a short paper in which you discuss this.
■ Writing Project
Consider the claim 'Killing another human being is always wrong.' Write a short essay (about
three pages, double-spaced) offering at least one argument for the claim and one against it.
Then discuss which judgments in your arguments are normative.
■ Chapter Summary
Principle of faithfulness: At all times, try to reconstruct an argument in a way that cap
tures the arguer's intentions-that is, premises and conclusion should say just what the
arguer intends them to say.
Principle of charity: At all times, make the argument as strong as possible-maximize the
truth of premises and conclusion, and the strength of the relation between them.
Rule for balancing faithfulness and charity: When there is a conflict between these two,
faithfulness takes priority.
Missing premise: Implicit premise that must be made explicit in reconstructing an
argument.
Extended argument: An argument with more than one conclusion.
Deductive argument: Its premises are offered as guaranteeing the conclusion.
Inductive argument: Its premises are offered as providing some support for its conclu
sion.
Normative judgment: Judgment to the effect that something has a certain value, or is
permissible, obligatory, or forbidden.
Normative argument: An argument with a normative judgment as its conclusion. It could
be aesthetic, legal, moral, or prudential.
Aesthetic judgment: It concerns evaluations or norms involving matters of taste.
Legal judgment: It concerns evaluations or norms involving what's permitted or obliga
tory or forbidden by law.
Moral judgment: It concerns evaluations or norms about what is ultimately good or bad,
right or wrong-not because it's sanctioned by the law, but because it deserves praise or
blame.
Prudential judgment: It concerns evaluations or norms about what is in one's own self
interest.
■ Key Words
Principle of charity
Principle of faithfulness
Missing premise
Extended argument
Inductive argument
Deductive argument
Normative argument
Prudential judgment
Aesthetic judgment
Moral judgment
Legal judgment
(/)
0
a:
0
�
>
w
�
CHAPTER
Evaluating Deductive
Arguments
In this chapter, you’ll look more closely at deductive reasoning, focusing first on the
concept of validity and then on related topics, including
The difference between valid and invalid arguments.
Some alternative ways of talking about validity.
The relation between validity and argument form.
How to represent propositional and categorical argument forms.
Soundness as an evaluative standard.
Deductive cogency as an evaluative standard.
The practical implications (or ‘cash value’) of validity, soundness, and cogency.
94
5.1 Validity
Sometimes people use ‘valid’ to mean ‘true’ or ‘reasonable’ and ‘invalid’ to mean ‘false’ or
‘unreasonable.’ But these are not what ‘valid’ and ‘invalid’ mean in logical thinking. A deductive
argument is valid if and only if its premises necessitate or entail its conclusion, where ‘entail
ment’ is defined as in Box 1.
As we’ve seen, a deductive argument is one in which the conclusion is supposed to follow neces
sarily from the premises-so that if the premises were all true, the conclusion would be, too.
Since a valid argument’s premises, if true, determine that the conclusion is true, valid arguments
can also be said to be truth-preserving. Any argument that fails to be truth-preserving would be
one whose premises could be true and its conclusion false at once. Such an argument is, by defi
nition, invalid: its premises do not entail its conclusion. Note that we’re introducing here some
different expressions that all mean the same thing. To say that an argument is valid is equivalent
to saying that its premises entail its conclusion. And both of these are equivalent to saying that
the argument is truth-preserving, and that its conclusion follows necessarily from its premise or
premises. The upshot of all this is:
In a valid argument, it makes no logical sense to accept the premises and reject
the conclusion.
Once you accept a valid argument’s premises, were you to reject its conclusion (i.e., think that it
is false), that would be contradictory or nonsensical. Contradictory statements cannot have the
same truth value: if one is true, the other must be false. Consider this valid argument:
1 If the Ohio River is in North America, then it is not in Europe. The Ohio River is in
North America; therefore it is not in Europe.
You cannot accept both that if the Ohio River is in North America, then it is not in Europe and also
that it is in North America and at the same time reject that the Ohio River is not in Europe. That
would be contradictory, thus making no logical sense.
Validity is one of the standards used to evaluate deductive arguments. Whether an argu
ment is valid or not is never a matter of degree, but instead one of all or nothing. An argument
cannot be ‘sort of valid.’ It’s either valid or it’s not. Furthermore, there is a simple test to deter
mine the validity of an argument. As you read it, ask yourself, ‘Could the conclusion be false
with all the premises true at once?’ If so, the argument flunks the test: it’s invalid. But if not,
then you may accept it as valid. Let’s consider some examples. Suppose we ventured to predict
what next summer in Baltimore will be like. We might say,
BOX 1 ■ ENTAILMENT
There is entailment in an argument if and only if the truth of the argument’s premises guarantees
the truth of its conclusion-in the sense that, if the premises are all true, the conclusion cannot be
false. Such an argument is valid and truth-preserving.
l[)
w
>
�
0
::)
0
w
0
C) (j)
z f_ z
f- w
<{ ::?
::) ::)
_J C)
;; a:
w <{
2 Next summer there will be some hot days in Baltimore. After all, according to
Baltimore's records for the last 100 years, nearly all summers have included some hot
days.
Or imagine that we want to decide what to expect on our European vacation. We might reason,
3 Yves is a Parisian and speaks French. The same is true of Odette, Mathilde, Marie,
Maurice, Gilles, Pierre, Jacques, and Jean-Louis. So, all Parisians speak French.
Now clearly in both arguments the conclusion could be false and the premises true.
Although the likelihood of that may seem exceedingly remote, it is possible. Both arguments
are therefore invalid. In claiming that false conclusions are 'possible,' we have in mind
logical possibility. Whether (2) and (3) would be likely to have true premises and false
conclusion in our actual world, with things being as they are, is beside the point. Rather, if
there is some scenario, 'possible' in the sense that it implies no internal contradiction, in
which these arguments' premises could be true and their conclusions false at once, then the
arguments are invalid.
At the same time, notice another thing: whether an argument is valid or not is entirely a
matter of whether its conclusion follows necessarily from its premises. The actual truth or
falsity of premises and conclusion in isolation is mostly irrelevant to an argument's validity.
What matters is whether the premises could be true and the conclusion false at once, because
that would determine the invalidity of the argument. Thus, a valid argument could have one or
more false premises and a true conclusion, as in
4 1. All dogs are fish.
2. All fish are mammals.
3. All dogs are mammals.
Or it could be made up entirely of false statements, as in
5 1. All Democrats are vegetarians.
2. All vegetarians are Republicans.
3. All Democrats are Republicans.
Validity is best thought of as a kind of relation between premises and conclusion in an
argument, where the actual truth or falsity of the component statements is largely irrele
vant. What matters is: do the premises necessitate the conclusion? If so, it's valid. If not, it's
invalid.
BOX 2 ■ VALID VS. INVALID ARGUMENTS
1. Arguments may be divided into two groups: those that are valid and those that are invalid.
2. Only valid arguments are truth-preserving: If their premises are true, then it is not possible for
their conclusion to be false.
3. Only in a valid argument do the premises entail the conclusion.
4. A logical thinker who accepts the premises of a valid argument cannot reject its conclusion
without contradiction. But this doesn't happen in the case of an invalid argument.
Valid Arguments and Argument Form
An argument form is the type of logical mold or pattern that each argument exemplifies. Often
the same argument form is the underlying pattern of many actual arguments. To show the
form of an argument, it is customary to replace some words in it by "place holders" or symbols
such as capital letters, keeping only the words that have a logical function. For example, in
(4) we could replace 'dogs' by 'A,' 'fish' by 'B,' and 'mammals' by 'C,' representing its argument
form as:
4' 1. All A are B
2. All B are C
3. All A are C
(4') is a valid argument form, because any argument with this underlying form would be valid:
if its premises were true, its conclusion would have to be true. Argument (s) above also exem
plifies this form-as does
6 1. All laptops are computers.
2. All computers are electronic devices.
3. All laptops are electronic devices.
Since (4) above likewise exemplifies argument form (4'), which is valid, therefore (4) is valid
. quite independent of the fact that its premises are false. For an argument to be valid, it is of no
importance whether it has all false premises, as in the case of (4), or a false conclusion with at
least one false premises as in (7) or even all false statements as in (5).
7 1. All professional soccer players are athletes.
2. All athletes are college students.
3. All professional soccer players are college students.
Since these arguments exemplify a valid argument form, they are valid. Their form is such that
any argument with true premises exemplifying it must have a true conclusion.
Validity and Argument Form
In any argument exemplifying a valid form, there is a relationship of entailment between
premises and conclusion. If the argument's premises are true, its conclusion cannot be
false. Validity consists in this relationship, and nothing more. The fact that an argument
might have one or more false premises is of no importance for its validity, which is entirely
a matter of argument form.
Invalidity is also a matter of argument form: an argument form is invalid if and only if an
argument with that form could have true premises and a false conclusion. But 'could' here
means 'logically possible,' which leaves open the possibility that a given invalid argument may
have true premises and a true conclusion. For instance,
>
I-
0
…J
<{
>
I.()
mlll
w >
lo :::,
0 w 0
0 (/)
z 1-_ z I- w
f–
0
__J
<( >
Lt)
w
>
j:::
0
::::l
0
w
0
0 (f)
� �
f— w
<( �
::::l ::::l
_J 0
� a:
w <(
-
SAMPLE ANSWER: Valid
2. New York, Toronto, Denver, Boston, Chicago, Minneapolis, Pittsburgh, Montreal, and Detroit are all
big cities in North America, and all of these cities have snow in winter. We may infer that all big North
American cities have snow in winter.
3. Since Mr. and Mrs. Gunderson are Republicans, their son Mark must be a Republican, too.
*4. All squares are polygons; for all squares are rectangles, and all rectangles are polygons.
5. All whales are fish, and some whales are members of the Conservative Party. Thus some fish are
members of the Conservative Party.
6. Isaac Newton wrote a book called Principia Mathematica. Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand
Russell wrote a book called Principia Mathematica. Hence, Russell, Whitehead, and Newton were
co-authors.
*7. No people who wear wool sweaters are cold. So Uncle Thorvald is never cold, because he always
wears a wool sweater.
8. Since beavers are nocturnal, we may infer that badgers, weasels, and wolverines are, too, for all of
these animals are small, fur-bearing mammals found in the upper Midwest.
9. Seven-year-old Jason has contracted chicken pox. This occurred only a week after his three younger
sisters, Gwendolyn, Samantha, and Hermione, were stricken with chicken pox. Consequently, Jason
caught the chicken pox from his sisters.
*10. Bart Simpson cannot run for governor of California because Bart Simpson is a cartoon character,
and no cartoon characters are citizens of California. Only citizens of California are eligible to run for
governor of California.
11. For as long as records have been kept, every winter there has been some rain in Vancouver.
Therefore, next winter there will be some rain in Vancouver.
12. Since Venus Williams and Serena Williams are star tennis players, and Venus and Serena are sisters ,
we may infer that at least two members of the Williams family are athletes; for all tennis stars are
athletes.
*13. Since this is a freshman-level course, it is an easy course, for all freshman-level courses are easy.
14. It is unlikely that Joe will be a senator. Most senators are people who win public debates, and so far
Joe has lost every one.
15. If my computer keeps crashing, then it must have picked up a virus somehow. Therefore, it must
have a virus, because it keeps crashing!
*16. The Washington Redskins is a football team that has thousands of enthusiastic fans. The same is
true of the Denver Broncos, the New York Jets, the Minnesota Vikings, and the Dallas Cowboys. It
follows that all American professional football teams have thousands of fans.
17. Since no health-conscious people are sedentary couch potatoes, no marathon runners are seden
tary couch potatoes, for all marathon runners are health-conscious people.
18. The value of stocks is now falling every day. Whenever this happens, stocks are not a good invest
ment. Thus stocks are not a good investment now.
*19. For us, the options tonight are either to watch a movie at home or go out for dinner. We won't watch
a movie at home. Thus we' ll go out for dinner.
20. Sally is always happy, because she is a singer, and many singers are always happy.
21. Nat is not a spy. All spies have espionage training, and he has never had such training.
*22. JJ's won't get the support of the Chamber of Commerce, for the Chamber of Commerce usually
supports only local firms, and JJ's is from out of state.
23. The Ethiopian city of Addis Ababa is a center of African culture. All cities that are centers of African
culture are large cities. Hence, Addis Ababa is a large city.
24. Either Syria will stop supporting Lebanon or it wants a war with Israel. But clearly Syria does not want
a war with Israel, so Syria will stop supporting Lebanon.
*25. Many undergraduates in the United States receive some form of financial aid. Since Jane is a college
undergraduate, she has financial aid.
26. An inspector at a Sony computer factory found that, out of the many computers she inspected, none
had defects. She concluded: 'At this factory, no computer is defective.'
27. Since it's a Friday, Atkins will not be home until late tonight. Most Fridays, Atkins makes a stop at
Miller's Bar and Grill on the way home for a beer or two and never leaves Miller's before 11 :00 p.m.
*28. Simon Peterson is a cardinal. Since no cardinals are Protestants, Peterson is not a Protestant.
29. Most people who have a tooth extracted without an anesthetic are in pain. I' ll have one extracted
without an anesthetic later today. Therefore, I' ll be in pain.
30. Mr. Abernathy must be at least sixty-five years old, since no one can be receiving Social Security
payments unless he is sixty-five years old or older, and Mr. Abernathy gets a Social Security check in
the mail every month.
Ill. For each of the above arguments that are valid, construct an argument of your
own that follows the same pattern. In this exercise, premises need not be true.
IV. Determine whether the following types of argument are logically possible or
impossible. For each that's logically possible, give an example.
1. A valid argument whose premises are true and conclusion false.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Logically impossible.
2. An invalid argument whose premises are true and conclusion false.
*3. An invalid argument whose premises are true and conclusion true.
4. An invalid argument form that cannot have true premises and a false conclusion.
*5. A valid argument whose premises are false and conclusion false.
6. A valid argument whose premises are false and conclusion true.
7. An invalid argument whose premises are false and conclusion false.
*8. An argument that is more or less valid.
>–
1-
0
_J
<( >
l!)
ml
w
>
i==
0
�
0
w
0
0 (/)
z 1-_ z I- w
<:( :::?: ��
_J 0
;; er: w <:(
V. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
Consider each of the following claims as a conclusion, and construct two arguments to support it, one
valid, the other invalid. (For the purposes of this exercise, premises need not be true.)
1. Joan is married.
2. Oranges are nutritious.
3. The Dodgers play well.
4. Laptops are not easy to break.
5. Sharks have gills.
6. Derek Jeter is wealthy.
7. Pelicans fly.
8. Iron expands when heated.
Propositional Argument Forms
As we have seen, another way to refer to valid arguments is as arguments that are truth
preserving. This is the same as saying that if their premises are true, then their conclusions
must also be true-or, equivalently, that the truth of their premises guarantees the truth of
their conclusions. Being truth-preserving is a characteristic a valid argument has in virtue of
the form or pattern it exemplifies. Some arguments have the characteristic of being truth
preserving because the statements that constitute their premises and conclusion are
connected in certain ways, forming distinctive patterns of relationship that transfer the truth
of the premises (if they are true) to the arguments' conclusions. Other arguments have it
because within the statements that constitute their premises and conclusions there are some
expressions, usually called terms, that bear certain relationships to each other that make the
arguments' conclusions true if the premises are true. Arguments of the former type are
propositional, those of the latter categorical.
We'll examine each type in more detail later, but before we go on, it's important to be clear
about what we mean by 'proposition.' Recall that a proposition is the content of a belief or state
ment, which has a truth value: it is either true or false. Let's now consider some propositional
arguments-that is, those for which being truth-preserving hinges on relations between the
propositions that constitute their premises and conclusions. For example,
1 0 1. If my cell phone is ringing, then someone is trying to call me.
2. My cell phone is ringing.
3. Someone is trying to call me.
(10) is a valid argument because of the relation among the propositions that make it up. Its
premise 1 features two simple propositions connected by 'if . . . then . . . ,' and its premise 2
asserts the first of those two simple propositions. After replacing each simple proposition in this
argument with capital letters used as symbols, keeping the logical connection, if . . . then . . . ,
(1o)'s argument form becomes apparent. It is
1 O' 1. If M, then C
2. M
3. C
In (10'), M stands for 'My cell phone is ringing' and C for 'Someone is trying to call me.' (10') is
not an argument but an argument form showing a certain relation between premises and con
clusion that is known as modus ponens. Any argument with this form exemplifies a modus po
nens. For example,
11 1. If thought requires a brain, then brainless creatures cannot think.
2. Thought requires a brain.
3. Brainless creatures cannot think.
Let's now consider other propositional argument forms. This argument has the logical form
modus tollens:
12 1. If there is growth, then the economy is recovering.
2. But the economy is not recovering.
3. There is no growth
This is revealed by symbolizing it as
12' 1. If G, then E
2. Not E
3. Not G
Box 4 offers a short list of some valid propositional argument forms, which we'll revisit in
Chapter 12. For now, let's illustrate the other forms in Box 4.
13 1. If inland temperatures increase, then crops are damaged.
2. If crops are damaged, then we all suffer.
3. If inland temperatures increase, then we all suffer.
BOX 4 ■ SOME VALID PROPOSITIONAL ARGUMENT FORMS
Modus Ponens
If P, then Q
p
Q.
Hypothetical Syllogism
If P, then Q
If Q, then R
If P, then R
Contraposition
If P, then Q
If not Q, then not P
Modus Tollens
If P, then Q
NotQ
NotP
Disjunctive Syllogism (1)
Either P or Q
NotP
Q.
Disjunctive Syllogism (2)
Either Par Q
NotQ
p
>–
1-
0
:::::i
<( >
w
>
i’.=
0
:::)
0 w
0
0 (fJ
z 1-_ z
I- w
<�
:::) :::)
_J 0
;; a:
w<
(13) is an instance of a hypothetical syllogism, for it has the form
13' 1. If I, then C
2. If C, then A
3. If I, then A
And, as you can prove for yourself, (14) and (15) below illustrate the two versions of disjunctive
syllogism in Box 4, while (16) illustrates contraposition:
14 1. Either American Dennis Tito or South African Mark Shuttleworth was the first
space tourist.
2. South African Mark Shuttleworth was not the first space tourist.
3. American Dennis Tito was the first space tourist.
15 1. Either American Dennis Tito or South African Mark Shuttleworth was the first
space tourist.
2. American Dennis Tito was not the first space tourist.
3. South African Mark Shuttleworth was the first space tourist.
16 1. If Persia was a mighty kingdom, then Lydia was a mighty kingdom.
2. If Lydia was not a mighty kingdom, then Persia was not a mighty kingdom.
All these arguments are substitution instances (or simply, instances) of one or another of the
argument forms in Box 4, which are all valid. This means that in any argument that is an
instance of one of these forms, there is entailment, no matter what actual statements the
symbols stand for. That is, no actual arguments of the forms listed in Box 4 above could have
true premises and a false conclusion. There are many such forms, but again, we'll examine this
topic at greater length in Chapter 12.
SUGGESTION: In this section, there are a number of valid argument forms. For quick
reference and to gain familiarity, construct a card with these forms. Write down on one
side those where validity hinges on relations among propositions, and on the other side
those where validity hinges on relations among terms.
Categorical Argument Forms
Many arguments are clearly valid, even though they don't fit into any form of propositional
logic. Consider
17 1. All dentists have clean teeth.
2. Dr. Chang is a dentist.
3. Dr. Chang has clean teeth.
(17) is plainly valid, for if its premises are true, then its conclusion must be true. Now suppose
we replace its parts by letter symbols, treating the argument as if it were an instance of an ar
gument form in propositional logic. We would then get this form:
17' 1. D
2. C
3. E
But (17') is an invalid form, since there are counterexamples to it: that is, arguments of the
same form with true premises and a false conclusion. Here is one,
18 1. Whales are mammals.
2. California is the most populous state in the United States.
3. The Earth is flat
So to take (17), a valid argument, to have an invalid argument form such as (17') would be in
correct. What's needed is a different system, one where letter symbols do not stand for propo
sitions. In other words, (17') is too coarse-grained to serve as the correct argument form of (17),
where the entailment hinges on relations among certain expressions within the propositions
that make up that argument, rather than on relations among the propositions themselves that
constitute premises and conclusion. In (17) the entailment depends on relations among terms
such as 'all,' 'Dr. Chang,' 'dentist' and 'clean teeth.'
A more fine-grained representation is needed for arguments such as (17). We shall repre
sent their forms by adopting the following conventions:
1. Use 'to be' in present tense as the main verb in each premise and conclusion.
2. Make explicit any logical expressions, such as 'all,' 'some,' and 'no.'
3. Replace expressions such as 'dentist' and 'clean teeth' with capital letters.
4. Replace expressions for specific things or individuals, such as 'Dr. Chang,' 'Fido,' 'I,' and
'that chair' with lowercase letters.
In this language, the logical form of (17) is similar to that of
19 1. All soda companies are businesses that prosper.
2. Pepsi is a soda company.
3. Pepsi is a business that prospers.
(19)'s argument form is
19' 1. All A are B.
2. c is an A.
3. cis a B
In (19'), 'A' stand for the term 'soda companies,' 'B' for 'businesses that prosper,' and 'c' for
'Pepsi.' We can also represent in this language arguments such as
20 1. All ophthalmologists are doctors.
2. Some ophthalmologists are short.
3. Some doctors are short.
>
I-
0
…..J
<{ >
w
>
f-
0
🙂
0
w
0
CJ (j)
z f
_ z
f- w
<( �
🙂 🙂
_J CJ
:; a:
w <(
-
(20) is a plainly valid argument: it is a substitution instance of a valid categorical argument
form.
Another instance of the same form is
21 1. All red squirrels are rodents.
2. Some red squirrels are wild animals.
3. Some rodents are wild animals.
The argument form of both (20) and (21) is,
20' 1. All A are B
2. Some A are C
3. Some B are C
Here 'A' stand for 'red squirrels' (or 'ophthalmologists'), 'B' for 'rodents' (or 'doctors'), and 'C' for
'wild animals' ( or 'short').
Let's now recall a point made at the beginning of this section: that another way to under
stand validity is to say that whether an argument is valid or not is simply a matter of whether
it has a valid form.
Consider
22 1. No Peloponnesians are Euboeans.
2. All Spartans are Peloponnesians.
3. No Spartans are Euboeans.
Even someone who knew nothing at all about Greek geography could nevertheless see that the
argument is valid, because it is an instance of the valid form number 3 in Box 5. No argument
with this form could have true premises and a false conclusion. Similarly, the following argu
ment is valid even though its premises are false. Why? Simply because it has valid form num
ber 3 in Box 5.
BOX 5 ■ SOME VALID CATEGORICAL ARGUMENT FORMS
1 2
All A are B Some A are B
No Bare C All A are C
No Care A Some Care B
3 4
NoAareB All A are B
All Care A All Care A
No Care B All Care B
5 6
All A are B All A are B
All Bare C Some A are not C
All A are C Some B are not C
23 1. All apples are oranges.
2. All bananas are apples.
3. All bananas are oranges.
Validity, then, is entirely a matter of argument form. The same could be said for the other ex
amples above. This brings us to another important point: for each form that is valid, all of the
arguments that have it will be valid. Similarly, for each invalid form, all of the arguments that
have it will be invalid.
Propositional or Categorical?
■ When you see certain connections between propositions, such as 'Either . . . or . . . '
and 'If ... then . . . ,' the argument is probably better reconstructed as propositional.
■ On the other hand, when you see in the premises certain words indicating quantity, such
as 'All,' 'No,' and 'Some,' the argument is probably better reconstructed as categorical.
The Cash Value of Validity
Logical thinking has goals, such as learning, understanding, and solving problems. Each of
these requires argument analysis and sometimes refutation, the process by which a given
argument is shown to fail. But, far from being among logical thinking's primary goals, refuta
tion is a result of argument analysis unavoidable in some cases. Achieving logical thinking's
primary goals greatly depends on charitable and faithful reconstruction of arguments. For
those that are deductive, charity recommends making them as strong as possible, maximizing
the truth of their premises and conclusion and the validity of their forms-while faithfulness
recommends trying to capture the arguer's intentions. In all of this, logical thinkers strive to
capture the form of an argument correctly, adding missing premises when needed. Once they
have properly reconstructed an argument, they then move on to evaluate it, keeping in mind
rules such as
■ Do not criticize/accept an argument by focusing solely on its conclusion.
■ Direct each objection to the argument form, or to a clearly identifiable premise.
■ Use the evaluative criteria offered here.
■ Do not make unsubstantial criticisms, such as 'that is a matter of opinion.'
Any challenge to validity is a challenge to the argument form. If the premises of an argument
with a certain form could be true and its conclusion false, then the argument is invalid because
it has an invalid form. Yet finding an argument invalid is not a conclusive reason to reject it,
since it could still be a good inductive argument (more on this in Chapter 6). Once an argu
ment is found valid, logical thinkers should then check whether its premises are true, a topic
we'll take up later in this chapter.
>
r–
0
_J
<( >
ma
UJ
r-
0
🙂
0
UJ
0
(.’J (/)
z r_ z
r- UJ
f-
0
::i
L!)
w
>
j::
0
:::i
0
w
0
CJ (/)
z 1-
_ z
I- w
<{ �
:::i :::i
_J CJ
;; a:
w <{
*2. Alaska is a large state in the United States. No large state in the United States is densely populated.
Thus, Alaska is not densely populated. (a, L, D)
3. All rattlesnakes are snakes. No snakes are friendly pets. Therefore, no rattlesnakes are friendly pets.
(R, S, P)
4. Some mathematicians are logicians. No logicians are space travelers. Thus some mathematicians
are not space travelers. (M, L, 1)
*5. All Afghans are peace-loving people. Some peace-loving people are French. Therefore, some
Afghans are French. (A, P, F)
6. All residents of the Vatican are religious believers. No religious believer is an atheist. Therefore, no
resident of the Vatican is an atheist. 0/, B, A)
7. Kate is not a tourist. All Niagara Falls visitors are tourists. It follows that Kate is not a Niagara Falls
visitor. (k, T, \/'i
*8. No Marine Corps drill instructors are sympathetic friends. So Sergeant Osberg is not a sympathetic
friend, since he is a Marine Corps drill instructor. (I, F, o)
IX. For each of the following arguments, determine whether it is propositional or
categorical.
1. All living creatures need liquid water. My cat is a living creature. Thus my cat needs liquid water.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Categorical argument
2. There is no extraterrestrial intelligence. After all, if there were extraterrestrial intelligence, we should
have evidence of it by now. But we don't have it.
*3. No desert is humid. The Atacama is a desert. Therefore, the Atacama is not humid.
4. Doctors are exposed to agents that cause ailments. Jane is a doctor. Hence, she is exposed to
agents that cause ailments.
*5. If the Orinoco crocodile is a rodent, then the Chinese alligator is a rodent. But the Chinese alligator is
not a rodent. Therefore, the Orinoco crocodile is not a rodent.
6. Euripides enjoyed tragedy. After all, all fifth-century Greeks enjoyed tragedy, and Euripides was a
fifth-century Greek.
*7. All hibernating mammals slow their breathing in the winter. Since all black bears are hibernating
mammals, therefore all black bears slow their breathing in the winter.
8. If one has poor health, one goes to the doctor. If one goes to the doctor, one spends money. Thus,
if one has poor health, one spends money.
*9. Chris will take summer courses this year, because either he takes them or he'll wait until next fall for
graduation, and he won't wait that long.
1 O. All diesel engines produce exhaust gases. All school buses have diesel engines. Thus all school
buses produce exhaust gases.
*11. The universe can act as a magnifying lens, since if relativity theory is correct, the universe can act as
a magnifying lens. And relativity theory is correct.
12. All people who drink a glass of warm milk before bedtime are sound sleepers. Given that Beth always
drinks a glass of warm milk before bedtime, she is a sound sleeper.
*13. All chameleons are lizards that change their color. All lizards that change their color are scary crea
tures. So all chameleons are scary creatures.
14. If crocodiles wallow in mud holes, then they are rarely killed by predators. Crocodiles do wallow in
mud holes. Thus they are rarely killed by predators.
*15. No Ohio farmer grows papayas, for no northern farmer grows papayas, and Ohio farmers are north
ern farmers.
X. The arguments below are either propositional or categorical. Indicate which is
which and give the argument form.
1. If the defendant's car was used in the robbery, then the car was at the scene of the crime. But it was
not at the scene of the crime. Thus the defendant's car was not used in the robbery. (D, C)
SAMPLE ANSWER: Propositional
If D, then C
NQ1_Q
Not D
2. If these snakes are cobras, then they're poisonous. Therefore, if these snakes are not poisonous,
then they are not cobras. (C, P)
3. If offenses against the innocent are punished, then we have a fair system of justice. If we have a fair
system of justice, then the guilty are treated as they deseNe. So if offenses against the innocent are
punished, then the guilty are treated as they deseNe. (0, J, G)
*4. Since all computers are mechanical devices, no computers are things that can think, for no things
that can think are mechanical devices. (C, D, T)
5. Archie doesn't eat chicken, for Archie is a vegan, and if he is a vegan, then he doesn't eat chicken.
(A, C)
*6. If Mississippi does allow gay marriage, then its laws governing marriage are liberal. In fact, its laws
governing marriage are not liberal. So, Mississippi does not allow gay marriage. (M, L)
7. Either doctors favor the new health program or the uninsured suffer. But doctors do not favor the
new health program. Hence the uninsured suffer. (N, U)
8. All accountants are good at math. Greg is not an accountant. Therefore, he is not good at math.
(A, M, g)
*9. If a flower is an orchid, then it is a tropical flower. Therefore, if it is not a tropical flower, then it is not
an orchid. (0, F)
10. Since no tropical country has blizzards and Venezuela is a tropical country, Venezuela doesn't have
blizzards. (C, B, v)
>
f–
0
__J
–
w
>
l
o
🙂
0
w
0
(‘.) (/)
��
I- w
<( � 🙂 🙂
_J ('.)
:; a:
w <(
11111B
*11. All babies are infants. Some babies are good at crawling. Therefore, some infants are good at crawl
ing. (B, I, C)
12. All carrots are vegetables full of vitamin A All vegetables full of vitamin A are foods good for your eye
sight. So carrots are foods good for your eyesight. (C, V, F)
*13. No schoolchildren are college graduates. All college graduates have a college diploma. Therefore, no
schoolchildren have a college diploma. (S, G, D)
14. If penguins are birds, then they are likely to have feathers. Since it is the case that penguins are birds,
we must conclude that they are likely to have feathers. (B, F)
*15. No planet is a star. Hence, Venus is not a star, since Venus is a planet. (P, S, v)
16. Anne is Mario's wife. Thus Mario is not a bachelor. For if Anne is his wife, then he is not a bachelor.
(A, B)
17. No professional gambler is good at saving money. Since Nathan is a professional gambler, we may
infer that he is not good at saving money. (G, M, n)
*18. If oxygen is the lightest element, then oxygen is lighter than hydrogen. But oxygen is not lighter than
hydrogen. Therefore, oxygen is not the lightest element. (0, H)
19. If Winston Churchill was English, then he was not Brazilian. But if he was not Brazilian, then he was
not South American. Thus if Winston Churchill was English, then he was not South American. (E, B, S)
*20. Melissa will either pledge Gamma Phi or she will not join a sorority at all this year. Accordingly, she will
not join a sorority at all, since she will not pledge Gamma Phi. (M, J)
XI. For each of the above arguments that is propositional, give the name of its form
(answers to 3, 6, 9, 18, and 20 in the back of the book).
SAMPLE ANSWER: 1. Modus to/lens
XII. Indicate whether the following statements are true or false.
1. A valid argument cannot have a false conclusion.
SAMPLE ANSWER: False
2. A valid argument cannot have a false premise.
*3. A valid argument cannot have true premises and a false conclusion.
4. Invalid arguments always have true premises and false conclusions.
*5. A valid argument could have a counterexample.
6. All valid argument forms are truth-preserving.
*7. An invalid argument could never have a true conclusion.
8. An invalid argument could never have true premises.
*9. If there is entailment in an argument, then that argument is truth-preserving.
10. An invalid argument could have no counterexample.
XIII.The following categorical arguments are invalid. After symbolizing their forms
accordingly, show invalidity in each case with a counterexample. (Tip: Use the
same counterexample for arguments exemplifying the same invalid form. When
the given argument plainly has true premises and a false conclusion, you can
simply point that out in lieu of counterexample.)
1. All female college students are students. Some students are smokers. Therefore, some female col
lege students are smokers.
SAMPLE ANSWER: All Fare D
Some o are M
Some Fare M.
Counterexample: F, D, and M stand for 'fish,' 'animal,' and 'mammal.' [All fish are animals. Some animals
are mammals. Thus some fish are mammals.]
2. All giraffes are mute. That animal is mute. Thus that animal is a giraffe.
*3. Most American citizens are permitted to vote in the United States. Michael is not permitted to vote in
the United States. So, Michael is not an American citizen.
4. Roses are flowers. Some flowers are daffodils. Thus roses are daffodils.
*5. No SUVs are easy to park. Some SUVs are speedy vehicles. Hence, no speedy vehicles are easy to
park.
6. Some days are rainy days. Some days are sunny days. Therefore, some rainy days are sunny days.
*7. Fido is a dog. Some dogs bark. Therefore, Fido barks.
8. Most Mexicans speak Spanish. Some non-Mexicans speak Spanish. Therefore, some non-Mexicans
are Mexicans.
9. All intellectuals support stem-cell research. Barbra Streisand supports stem-cell research. Therefore,
Barbra Streisand is an intellectual.
10. No desktop computer is light. My computer is not light. Hence, my computer is not a desktop.
XIV. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. Explain in your own words the relation between 'invalidity' and 'counterexample.'
2. Explain in your own words the claim that validity is a matter of argument form.
3. Give two arguments of your own for each of the following valid argument forms: modus ponens,
modus to/lens, hypothetical syllogism, disjunctive syllogism, and contraposition.
4. Give a counterexample to the following argument: Horses are domestic animals. Dobbin is a domes
tic animal. Therefore, Dobbin is a horse.
5. For each of the following argument forms, construct an argument with true premises on a topic of
your choice that illustrates that form:
1. All A are B
AIIB areC
AIIA areC
>–
1-
0
__J
<( >
,ti
111111
w
:J
0
w
0
C) Cf)
zr-_z
f- w
<�
:J :J
_J 0
;; a:
w<
11111
2. All A are B
Some A are not C
Some B are not C
3. No As are Bs
All Care A
No Care B
4. All A are B
Some A are C
Some B are C
5. AIIA areB
c is not a B
c is not an A
6. AIIA areB
c is an A
c is a B
6. For each of the following argument forms, construct an argument with true premises on a topic of
your choice that illustrates that form: modus ponens, modus to/lens, contraposition, hypothetical
syllogism, and disjunctive syllogism.
5.2 Soundness
Must we then always accept the conclusions of valid arguments? No, for there may still be
something wrong with them (as is clear in some of the examples above). To evaluate an argu
ment, validity is the first criterion we use, but not the only one. After we have decided that an
argument is valid, we must also determine whether it is sound, bearing in mind that
An argument is sound if and only if it is valid and all of its premises are true.
Thus consider some arguments given earlier:
22 1. No Peloponnesians are Euboeans.
2. All Spartans are Peloponnesians.
3. No Spartans are Euboeans.
4 1. All dogs are fish.
2. All fish are mammals.
3. All dogs are mammals.
5 1. All Democrats are vegetarians.
2. All vegetarians are Republicans.
3. All Democrats are Republicans.
BOX 7 ■ SOUND ARGUMENT
1. An argument is sound if and only if it is valid and all of its premises are true.
2. An argument is unsound if it lacks either validity or true premises, or both.
3. Unsoundness is a reason to reject an argument even if it's valid.
4. The conclusion of a sound argument is true.
5. Given (4), a sound argument's conclusion cannot be rejected without saying something false.
Argument (22) is sound. But (4) and (5) are unsound. This is because if an argument lacks
either validity or true premises (or both), then it is unsound. The problem with (4) and (s) is that
their premises are false, thus rendering the arguments unsound, even though, as we have
seen, both are valid. Important things to remember are, first, that if even one of an argument's
premises is false, then the argument is unsound, whether it's valid or not. Second, a premise
counts as true only if there is no controversy about whether it's true. Third, since validity is a
necessary condition of soundness, an argument can also be unsound because its form is
invalid. For example,
26 1. Any city that is the capital of a country is a center of political power.
2. Chicago is a center of political power.
3. Chicago is the capital of a country.
Here both premises are true, yet the argument is unsound because it is invalid.
Validity and true premises, then, are the necessary conditions for soundness. The ques
tion of whether an argument's premises are in fact true or false is another matter entirely
(which cannot be answered by logic alone). Most such answers belong rather to the sciences,
or to the investigations of historians, geographers, and other fact finders. To be sure, a good
logical thinker will want to get her facts straight! But this is where she must head for the
library or the laboratory and consider the evidence for the premises of arguments that
purport to be sound.
BOX 8 ■ SOUNDNESS
DEDUCTIVE
ARGUMENT
SoUND
UNSOUND
Valid with all true
premises
Invalid
At least one false
premises
Invalid and at
least one false
premises
(/)
(/) w
z
0
z
::J
0
(/)
N
l()
w
>
f-
0
::J
0
w
0
CD CJ)
z f
_ z
f- w
<:�
::J ::J
_J CD
;; er:
w <:
The Cash Value of Soundness
Why, then, is soundness so important? Why is soundness a desirable characteristic in argu
ments? Because if one is aware of an argument's soundness, then not only is one fully justified
in accepting its conclusion, one has to accept it! As defined above, all valid arguments are
truth-preserving-if their premises are true, their conclusions must be true. If an argument is
valid and also actual!}, has true premises, it is sound; and that means that the truth of the prem
ises transfers to the conclusion. Thus there is no denying the conclusion of any such argument
without saying somethingfalse.
Soundness has a practical impact or worth because whenever a given deductive argument
meets this standard, its conclusion is guaranteed to be true. In fact, the cash value of sound
ness is twofold:
When an argument is sound, then
■ Given its validity, you can't assert its premises and deny its conclusion without saying
something contradictory.
■ Given its validity and its true premises, you can't deny its conclusion without saying
something false.
What about unsoundness? What is its cash value for logical thinkers? An unsound argument
fails to guarantee the truth of its conclusion. If an argument is valid but unsound, that means
that it has at least one false premise. The realization of this is sufficient reason to reject that
argument. If an argument is unsound but has all true premises, that means that its argument
form is invalid: as we'll see in Chapter 6, some such arguments are better considered inductive
and evaluated according to standards other than soundness.
5.3 Cogency
Validity and soundness are not the only standards used to evaluate deductive arguments.
There is also deductive cogency or persuasiveness, a standard that is met when a proposed
argument has
BOX 9 ■ THREE CONDITIONS FOR COGENCY
1. Recognizable validity.
2. Acceptable premises.
3. Premises that are more clearly acceptable than the conclusion.
Given 1, the validity of a cogent argument should be clear to the logical thinker evaluating
the argument. Given 2 and 3, the premises of a cogent argument should provide the logical
thinker with good reasons to accept its conclusion. Note that this falls short of requiring that
the cogent argument be sound: that is, an unsound argument could be cogent, provided that
the thinker recognizes its validity and takes the premises to provide good reasons for its con
clusion, even when, unknown to the thinker, at least one of its premises happens to be false.
Consider a thinker who seems to have seen Ingrid at the library and reasons as follows:
27 1. Ingrid is at the library.
2. If Ingrid is at the library, then she is not at the cafeteria.
3. Ingrid is not at the cafeteria.
Since he just saw Ingrid at the library, he seems to have evidence that premise 1 is true. 2 is also
true, since nobody could be in two different places at the same time. From 1 and 2 together,
conclusion 3 follows validly by modus ponens. So the argument is deductively cogent: it is
recognizably valid and has acceptable premises that support the conclusion. But suppose that in
fact, unknown to the thinker, it wasn't Ingrid at all he saw in the library but her identical twin,
Greta. In this situation, the argument is unsound-but still perfectly cogent!
On the other hand, there can sometimes be sound arguments that are non-cogent. For
having recognizable validity and true premises might not be enough for an argument to be
persuasive. Consider:
28 1. The Earth is not flat and is not the center of the universe.
2. The Earth is not the center of the universe
(28) is plainly valid, since if its premise is true, its conclusion cannot be false. Moreover, since its
premise is in fact true, the argument is also sound. But anyone who reasonably doubted (28)'s
conclusion would not be persuaded to accept it. (28) fails to meet condition 3 above: namely, hav
ing a premise that is more clearly acceptable than the conclusion. Imagine this argument being
offered in the Middle Ages, when all available evidence pointed to the falsity of its conclusion.
Even though people at that time would have rejected premise 1, unknown to them that premise
was true-and the argument sound. Thus even sound arguments can fail to be cogent when
their premises fail to be more acceptable than the conclusion they are offered to support.
BOX 10 ■ SECTION SUMMARY
A deductive argument meeting the three conditions of cogency in Box 9 is one whose premises
give the logical thinker good reasons to accept its conclusion.
The Cash Value of Cogency
Anyone who recognizes the validity of an argument and finds its premises to provide good
reasons for its conclusion cannot rationally reject the argument. Such an argument may be
said to be 'rationally compelling' (or simply 'compelling'). If the thinker were to reject the
argument, that would be irrational: it would make no logical sense. Since argument (28) cannot
persuade thinkers to accept its conclusion on the basis of its premises, the argument is not co
gent (i.e., not rationally compelling). Logical thinkers should be on guard for such arguments
and strive to avoid them altogether. In Chapter 8 we'll discuss a pattern of mistake in arguing
that affects the cogency of some valid, and even sound, arguments.
>–
0
z w
CJ
0
0
l()
11111
l1J
>
f–
0
🙂
0
l1J
0
CJ (/)
��
f– l1J
<( � 🙂 🙂
__J CJ
;;: a:
l1J <(
Exercises
1 . What does it mean to say that a deductively cogent argument is rationally compelling?
2. Explain the difference between soundness and cogency.
3. Given a certain standard for deductive arguments, it is contradictory to assert the premises of
an argument that satisfies it and yet at the same time deny the conclusion. What standard is
that?
4. What's the effect of denying the conclusion of sound argument?
5. What's the effect of denying the conclusion of an argument that one recognizes as cogent?
6. Must the conclusion of an invalid argument always be rejected? Explain your answer.
XVI. Which of the following statements are true, and which are false?
1 . An unsound argument could have a valid form
SAMPLE ANSWER: True
•2. A sound argument could have all false premises.
3. A sound argument could have one false premise.
*4. A sound argument could be invalid.
5. An unsound argument could have a true conclusion.
*6. A sound argument could have a false conclusion.
7. A sound argument could have true premises and true conclusion.
*8. A sound argument could have a true conclusion.
XVII. What's the matter with the following arguments? Explain.
1. An argument whose premises entail its conclusion is valid. Hence, one should accept the conclusion
of any valid argument.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Such an argument could be non-cogent, or have false premises and thus be unsound.
•2. Only sound arguments guarantee the truth of their conclusions. Thus entailment and therefore valid
ity are of no importance.
3. Logic books make too much fuss about soundness. After all, unsound arguments may also have
true conclusions.
*4. Validity doesn't matter in science, for science values truth, and there is no relation between validity
and truth.
XVIII. Indicate whether the following scenarios are logically possible or impossible:
1. An unsound argument where there is entailment
SAMPLE ANSWER: Logically possible (a valid argument with at least one false premise)
2. An unsound argument with a false conclusion
3. A valid argument where there is no entailment
*4. A sound argument that is not truth-preserving
5. An argument that is an instance of a valid form
*6. An invalid argument with true premises and a false conclusion
7. A sound argument with false premises and a true conclusion
*8. An unsound argument with false premises and a false conclusion
9. A sound argument where there is no entailment
*10. A cogent argument that is not rationally persuasive
11 . A cogent argument that is invalid
*12. A cogent argument that is unsound
XIX. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. For any possible arguments in the previous exercise, provide an example of your own.
2. Give two examples of your own to illustrate the following: modus ponens, contraposition, and dis
junctive syllogism.
3. Explain why your examples above are valid.
4. Explain each of the following claims:
A. Denying the conclusion of a cogent argument is irrational.
B. Asserting the premises while denying the conclusion of a valid argument is contradictory.
C. Some valid arguments might not be cogent.
D. Some unsound arguments might not be cogent.
E. Some unsound arguments might be cogent.
F. A deductively valid argument might yet be clearly unsound.
5. Illustrate each of the statements above with an example, supplying the context when needed.
■ Writing Project
Find two arguments on the issue of immigration policy, one supporting tighter restrictions on
undocumented aliens, the other opposing them. The sources, which should be identified in
your work, may be biogs or articles from a website, a newspaper, or a magazine. First, recon
struct the arguments as deductive, and then discuss whether they are sound. The simpler the
argument, the easier it is to determine whether it is sound. A length of 700 words should be
adequate.
f--
0
w
---,
0
a:
0...
(9
z
t::
a:
w
>
i=
0
::J
0
w
0
CJ (j)
z 1-_ z
I- w
<( �
::J ::J
-;j_ CJ
> a:
w <(
IEI
■ Chapter Summary
Propositional argument: the relation of inference hinges on relations among the propo
sitions expressed by its premises and conclusion.
Categorical argument: the relation of inference hinges on relations among the terms
within its premises and conclusion.
Argument form: the symbolic pattern of the logical relations in an argument.
Counterexample to an argument: another argument of the same form with clearly true
premises and a false conclusion. It proves that the original argument has an invalid
form.
Substitution instance of an argument form: an actual argument exemplifying that form.
Some valid forms of propositional arguments: modus ponens, modus tollens, hypothetical
syllogism, disjunctive syllogism, and contraposition.
Validity, soundness, and cogency: standards for evaluating deductive arguments.
VALIDITY
Definition
An argument is valid if and on!}> if it has entailment (its premises necessitate its conclusion).
Cash Value
■ It is not possible that the argument’s premises are true and its conclusion false.
■ The conclusion could be false, if at least one of the premises is false.
■ It is contradictory to accept a valid argument’s premises and reject its conclusion.
SOUNDNESS
Definition
An argument is sound if and on!)> if it is valid and all its premises are true.
Cash Value
■ The argument’s conclusion is true: to deny it is to say something false.
■ A logical thinker who recognizes an argument as sound must accept its conclusion.
COGENCY
Definition
An argument is cogent if and on!)> if it is recognizab!J valid and has acceptable premises which
are more acceptable than the conclusion they attempt to support.
Cash Value
■ Any argument that satisfies these conditions is rationally compelling, in the sense that
it would move the thinker to accept its conclusion (provided she accepts its premises
and works out the entailment).
■ It would be irrational for the thinker to reject the conclusion of that argument.
■ Key Words
Validity
Entailment
Truth-preserving argument
Argument form
Propositional argument
Categorical argument
Soundness
Counterexample
Substitution instance
Cogency
w
::<'.'.
CHAPTER
Analyzing Inductive
Arguments
This chapter looks more closely at inductive reasoning. Among its topics are:
The nature of inductive arguments.
Universal and non-universal generalizations.
Identifying types of inductive argument: enumerative induction, statistical syllogism,
■ causal argument, and analogy.
Two standards for evaluating inductive arguments: reliability and strength.
Mill's methods for establishing causal connections between events: agreement and
difference, and concomitant variation.
122
6.1 Reconstructing Inductive Arguments
Since we have already dwelt at some length on deductive arguments, in this chapter we turn to
inductive ones, which are crucial to ordinary and scientific reasoning. As we have seen, an
argument is either deductive or inductive, depending whether the premises guarantee the
truth of the conclusion. If they do, the argument is deductive; if not, it's inductive. There are a
number of related tests that may help in recognizing an inductive argument. First, in the case
of any such argument, ask yourself
Could the premises of the argument be asserted and the conclusion denied without logical
contradiction?
■ If yes, the argument is inductive.
■ If no, the argument is deductive.
Let's consider some examples-first, a simple deductive argument:
1 Pam is energetic and athletic. Therefore, Pam is athletic.
The first test recommends trying to see what happens when (1)'s premises are asserted and its
conclusion denied. The test yields
2 Pam is energetic and athletic. But Pam is not athletic.
(2) is contradictory: there is no logically possible scenario in which the statements that make
up (2) could all be true or all false at once. In light of such a result, argument (1) above is
deductive. By contrast, consider
3 1. Pam is athletic.
2. Most of those who are athletic don't eat junk food.
3. Pam doesn't eat junk food.
Argument (3)'s premises could all be asserted and its conclusion denied without contradiction.
After all, there are possible scenarios in which these premises are true and the conclusion false
for example, a scenario in which Pam is athletic, and most athletic people do not eat junk food, but
Pam does eat junk food. Thus (3) is inductive. Similarly, (4) and (s) are inductive, given that their
premise could be asserted and their conclusion denied without contradiction:
4 1. Many horses are friendly.
2. Mr. Ed is a horse.
3. Mr. Ed is friendly.
5 Housing prices will continue to go down, for we are having a recession and usually
housing prices go down in recessions.
w
>
l
o
:J
0
z
(‘)
z
l
o
:J
a:
1–
(j) (j)
z 1-
oz
0W wz
a: :J
� a:
co <(
Ell
(/)
f
z w
� =>
(‘) a:
<(
w
>
i=
0 => 0
z
(‘)
z
N
�
<( z
<(
lllfD
Compare (4) with (6),
6 1. All horses are friendly.
2. Mr. Ed is a horse.
3. Mr. Ed is friendly.
(6) is deductive, since it is not possible to assert its premises and deny its conclusion without
contradiction. If we try to do so, we would be saying something contradictory, namely,
7 All horses are friendly. Mr. Ed is a horse. But Mr. Ed is not friendly.
There is no possible scenario where all three statements could be true at once. For if it is true
that all horses are friendly and that Mr. Ed is a horse, it must be false that he is not friendly.
Notice that in a deductive argument, its conclusion doesn't add any information that was not
already in the premises. By contrast, an inductive argument always involves an inferential leap,
for its conclusion invariably conveys information that was not given in the premises. Thus its
conclusion is not strictly contained in its premises. But this feature makes inductive arguments
ideally suited for scientific reasoning in fields such as physics and biology, where scientists
often make causal connections or reach general conclusions on the basis of only a sample of
observed cases. The observation that a great number of metals expand under heat plays a role in
the scientists' conclusion that all metals do so-as does research on the habits of people with
lung disease in their concluding that smoking increases the risk of contracting such ailments.
But both conclusions add something that was not among the scientists' premises.
Another distinctive feature of inductive arguments is that newly acquired evidence could
always make a difference in the degree of support for their conclusions, strengthening it in
some cases, weakening it in others. Consider
8 1. 98% of State College students are involved in politics.
2. Heather is a State College student.
3. Heather is involved in politics.
Argument (8) is inductive. Its premises, if true, would provide some support for its conclusion.
New evidence to the effect that Heather is indifferent to politics, however, could undermine
that support. Once that evidence is added, the argument then is
9 1. 98% of State College students are involved in politics.
2. Heather is a State College student.
3. Heather never votes.
4. Heather is involved in politics.
A quick comparison of (8) and (9) shows that in the latter, support for the claim that Heather is
involved in politics has been undermined by the addition of premise 3.
The features of inductive arguments so far reviewed suggest that there is no entailment in
them: their premises, even in cases where they succeed in supporting their conclusions, could
never necessitate them. That is, no inductive argument is truth-preserving. Although an
inductive argument may in fact have true premises and a true conclusion, what makes the
argument inductive is that an argument of the same form could have true premises and a false
conclusion-which, again, is the same as saying that the premises of an inductive argument
do not entail its conclusion. Yet, as we shall see in this chapter, the lack of entailment in
inductive arguments does not mean that they cannot offer support for their conclusions.
In fact, they often make their conclusions probably true, or reasonable to believe, by providing
evidence for them, even though their premises always fall short of necessitating their
conclusions. This is why it is common to refer to the premises of inductive arguments as
'evidence.' At the same time, since the conclusions of such arguments may be supported but
are never completely proved true by the premises, they have the status of conjectures and are
often called 'hypotheses.'
Given these features, inductive arguments are plausibility arguments. That is, although the
evidence that any such argument may provide for its hypothesis never entails that hypothesis,
when successful, they can make it plausible. To say that a claim is plausible is to say that it is
likely to be true, probably true, or at least reasonable to accept. We shall look closely at the
standard for successful induction once we have examined some common types of inductive
argument. Before leaving this section, however, it is important that you know the answers to
the questions in Box 1.
BOX 1 ■ INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS
What sort of argument counts as inductive?
■ Any argument whose premises may provide evidence for its conclusion or hypothesis but do
not guarantee it.
How does one determine whether an argument is inductive or not?
By checking
■ whether it would be possible for an argument with the same form to have true premises
and a false conclusion.
■ whether one can assert its premises and deny its conclusion without contradiction.
■ whether the conclusion adds information not contained in the premises.
If in any case the answer is Yes, then the argument is inductive.
6.2 Some Types of Inductive Argument
Enumerative Induction
Of the four types of inductive argument discussed in this chapter, we'll begin with
enumerative induction. An enumerative induction always has a universal conclusion to the
effect that all things of a certain kind have (or lack) a certain feature. This conclusion is
drawn from evidence that some things of that kind have (or lack) that feature.
The conclusion of any such argument, often called an 'inductive generalization,' is a
universal generalization:
UJ
>
I
()
::,
0
z
u.
0
(/)
UJ
ll.
>-
I- 1-
UJ z
� UJ
0�
(/) ::,
(\J CJ . a:
co <(
Cf)
r
z w
�
:::,
(.'J er
<(
w
>
r
0
:::,
0
z
(.’J
z
N
�
<(
z
<(
A universal generalization
Consider
■ is a statement asserting that all of the members of a certain class have (or don't have)
a certain feature.
■ may be expressed by a great number of different patterns of sentence. Some standard
patterns are 'All ... are ... ,' 'Every ... is ... ,' 'No ... is ... .'
1 0 Roses blossom in the summer.
Unless more information is provided here, (10) should be read as saying 'All roses blossom in
the summer,' which illustrates the pattern 'All A are B.'
To support (10) with an enumerative induction, we may adopt one or the other of two equiv
alent strategies. First, offer a single premise to the effect that, for example, many roses have been
observed to blossom in the summer. That would be a non-universal generalization:
A non-universal generalization
■ is a statement asserting that some, perhaps many, of the members of a class have
(don 't have) a certain feature.
■ may be expressed by a great number of different patterns of sentence. Some standard
patterns are 'Most ... are ... ,' 'A few ... are ... ,' 'Many ... are ... ,' 'n percent of .. .
are ... '(where n percent is less than 100 percent), 'Some ... are ... ,' and 'Some .. .
are not. .. .'
According to this strategy, the argument would run:
11 1. Many roses have been observed to blossom in the summer.
2. All roses blossom in the summer.
Why is conclusion 2 a universal generalization? Because it asserts that all things of a certain
kind (roses) have a certain feature (blossoming in the summer). Here are other such general
izations common in science and everyday life:
12 Every metal expands when heated.
13 Any potato has vitamin C.
14 Each body falls with constant acceleration.
15 All bodies attract each other in proportion to their masses and in inverse proportion
to the square of the distance between them.
16 No emeralds are blue.
17 No seawater quenches thirst.
18 No mules are fertile.
Following the above strategy, we could attempt to support these generalizations by
enumerative induction. Clearly, scientists could not have observed all metals in order to
conclude (12), so the premise for (12) must be a non-universal generalization saying, for
example, that many metals so far observed expand when heated. Similar enumerative
inductions support the other universal generalizations in our list. Each such enumerative
induction would have a premise that would be a non-universal generalization to the effect
that things of the relevant kind have (12 through 15) or do not have (16 through 18) a
certain feature.
An alternative, yet equivalent, strategy to support these universal generalizations by
enumerative induction would have specific statements as premises.
A specific statement is a statement about an individual thing or person. For example:
'Benjamin Franklin founded the University of Pennsylvania,' 'That oak is infested,' 'Mary's
cap is waterproof,' and 'The UN is in session.'
If we wish to use this strategy to support the conclusion that roses blossom in the summer, our
argument may run:
19 1. Rose 1 has been observed to blossom in the summer.
2. Rose 2 has been observed to blossom in the summer.
3. Rose 3 has been observed to blossom in the summer ...
4. Rose number n, has been observed to blossom in the summer.
5. All roses blossom in the summer.
When n is a large number (say, billions) of individual roses, the universal generalization in con
clusion 5 would be supported by the argument's premises, each of which is a specific statement
about individual roses found to blossom in the summer. This strategy is equivalent to the one used
in (n) above, given that (19)'s premises spell out what (n)'s premise summarizes. Similar to (n) is
20 1. Every raven so far observed has been black.
2. Ravens are black.
Argument (2o)'s conclusion is a universal generalization ascribing a certain feature (blackness)
to all ravens. Like other inductive arguments, this makes an inferential leap: from a number of
ravens having a certain feature, it draws the conclusion that all ravens have that feature. Its
premise, if true, supports the claim that a great number of ravens have that feature, but it does
not guarantee that all ravens do. After all, nobody can observe all past, present, and future
ravens! Argument (2o)'s conclusion, then, goes beyond the information given in its premise.
Inductions of this sort run along the lines of (21).
21 1. A number, n, of A have been observed to be B
2. All A are B
Clearly, any argument with this form could have a true premise and a false conclusion, since it
is always possible that some unobserved A lacks the feature of being a B. This could happen
even in cases where n turns out to be a very large number. Note that if n were taken to involve
all cases, the argument would be deductive.
w
>
i=
0
🙂
0
z
LL
0
(/) w
(]._
f- fw z
2W
02
(/) 🙂
N CJ . 0::
(.’)
a:
l
o
::)
0
z
(.’)
z
N
i==
0
🙂
0
z
LL
0
I- 1-w z
�w
0�
(/) 🙂
NC) . 0:
co
�
0
:::,
0
z
0
z
N
<(
z
<(
Causal Argument
It is a matter of well-documented observation that whenever a flame comes in contact with
combustible substances, this is invariably followed by a fire. Given that evidence, we may
safely conclude that Jim lighting a match this morning near the gas caused the fire that
erupted immediately after. Here we reason from an observed effect (the fire) to a possible
cause that we may, or may not, have observed (Jim lighting a match this morning near the
gas). Parallel causal reasoning is at work when only the effects of an event have been
observed and we infer from them their likely cause-as is not uncommon in crime investi
gations. Other times, facts have been observed pertaining to the cause of an event and these
are then used in causal reasoning to predict possible effects, as in recent medical research
that has revealed certain genes likely to be responsible for a type of mental illness mani
festing as a social pathology. Here the genes appear to be a likely cause, in the sense that
their presence is necessary (though not sufficient) for developing the social pathology. After
all, not everyone with the genes will develop the illness: other factors, including environ
mental ones, would also be needed. In the explosion case, Jim's lighting of a match this
morning near the gas was sufficient but not necessary for the explosion to occur: in the
described circumstances, an action of that sort would invariably cause an explosion, but
other types of action could also cause an explosion.
Knowledge of the causal relations between events is instrumentally valuable for us,
because the control of nature is essential for human survival and flourishing. From a
prudential point of view, we wish to promote those causes that have good effects while
preventing those that have bad effects. Knowing that droughts were causally related to failed
crops spurred the early development of irrigation systems by engineers, and farmers in
antiquity. Similarly, our prospect of learning about causal connections between certain micro
organisms and illnesses has triggered medical research that has resulted in our being able to
prevent or contain infections and deadly diseases such as malaria and polio. So it is not an
exaggeration to say that much of our everyday lives and scientific progress depend greatly on
our being able to make causal connections between things and events.
We take some phenomena (things and occurrences of things) to be the effects or results of
other phenomena, which are their causes, and reason accordingly, ascribing causal relationships
to new phenomena that we encounter. Reasoning about how certain events stand in cause/effect
relations with other events takes the form of causal arguments:
A causal argument makes the claim that two or more things or events are causally related
in any of these ways:
1. Y results from Z.
2. Y causes Z.
3. Y and Z are the cause or the effect of another thing X
The reasoning underwriting causal arguments is fundamental to both commonsense and
scientific knowledge. It is at work when, if presented with some empirical evidence of state
of affairs E, we set out to discover how E came to be. This requires determining which state
of affairs C is linked to E-as its sufficient cause, its necessary cause, or its necessary and
sufficient cause- for the word 'cause' can be used to mean a number of different
relationships. When used to talk about a phenomenon that is always enough to bring about
a certain outcome all by itself, it means sufficient cause, as illustrated by this causal
argument:
32 1. There was a power blackout in my neighborhood yesterday.
2. My computer malfunctioned yesterday.
3. Yesterday's blackout was responsible for the malfunctioning of my computer.
In (32), yesterday's blackout is taken to be the sufficient cause of the malfunctioning of the
computer-just as overcooking one's dinner is sufficient for spoiling it. But the blackout isn't a
necessary cause of the computer malfunctioning, because in the absence of a power blackout,
the computer could still malfunction because of some other condition, such as rough
handling, obstructed ventilation, and defective parts.
Other times, an event C is the necessary cause of another event E, which is to say that E
cannot occur in the absence of C. Since AIDS cannot occur in the absence of HN, this is the
sense of 'cause' at work in the claim that
33 HN causes AIDS.
There is also a sense of 'cause' that denotes a condition that is both necessary and sufficient to
bring about a certain effect: that would be the case of a cause that's enough all by itself to cause
something to happen and also necessary, in the sense that the effect could not have happened
without it-as when we say that
34 Having the genome of a cat causes Fluffy the kitten to grow up to be a cat.
Here, having a certain genetic code is both a necessary cause for the animal to be a cat (rather
than, say, a monkey) and a sufficient cause, since it will always produce the same result.
Note, however, that causal claims could be a generalization such as (33), or a particular
statement such as (34) and the conclusion of (32). But when arguers make particular causal
claims, their claims often rest on implicit generalizations. In the case of (32), it's a missing
premise that could be reconstructed as being either a universal or a non-universal
generalization. If the former, the argument would be deductive; if the latter, inductive. As an
inductive argument, it could run this way:
32' 1. Power blackouts are often the cause of computer malfunctions.
2. There was a power blackout in my neighborhood yesterday.
3. My computer malfunctioned yesterday.
4. Yesterday's blackout was responsible for my computer's malfunction.
(32')'s conclusion has the status of a hypothesis, which would be well supported, provided its
premises are true. Because, as reconstructed here, (32' )'s premises don't guarantee its
conclusion, the argument is inductive.
w
>
l
o
:::J
0
z
LL
0
(/)
w
(l_
I- 1-
w z
::;;;w
0::;;;
(/) :::J
CJ NCI:
co
f–
0
:::J
0
z
(!J
z
N
<(
z
<(
BOX 3 ■ THREE MEANINGS OF 'CAUSE'
1. Sufficient cause: C is a sufficient cause of E if and only if C always produces E.
2. Necessary cause: C is a necessary cause of E if and only if E cannot occur in the absence of C.
3. Necessary and sufficient cause: C is a necessary and sufficient cause of E if and only if C always
is the sole cause of E.
The methods of agreement and difference, and of concomitant variation. In his System of
Logic (1843), John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) made use of ordinary intuitions in an attempt to
establish generalizations about cause-and-effect relations. According to those intuitions,
whenever something occurs, it is often possible to narrow the range of acceptable hypotheses
about its likely cause-or about its effect-by eliminating plainly irrelevant factors until at
last we find the hypothesis most likely to be the actual cause (or effect) of the occurrence. Of
the five methods to establish generalizations about causal relationships proposed by Mill,
we'll here consider two: the so-called method of agreement and difference and the method of
concomitant variation.
The method of agreement and difference The method of agreement and difference rests on
the following basic principles:
1. Agreement: What different occurrences of a certain phenomenon have in common is
probably its cause.
2. Difference: Factors that are present only when some observed phenomenon occurs are
probably its cause.
Suppose a coach wants to find out why Mick, Jim, and Ted, three of his best players, often
perform poorly on Friday afternoons. After collecting some data about what each player does
before the game, the coach reasons along these lines:
35 1. Mick,Jim, and Ted have been performing poorly on Friday afternoons.
2. Going to late parties on Thursday is the one and only thing that all three do when
and only when they perform poorly.
3. Going to late parties on Thursday likely causes their poor game performance.
The coach's reasoning here illustrates 'agreement,' since it runs roughly alone these lines:
36 1. X has occurred several times.
2. Y is the one and only other thing that precedes all occurrences of X.
3. Y causes X.
But to make a more precise cause-effect claim, the coach should also use the method of
difference: first, he should compare the players' performance when they've been going to late
parties and when they haven't, and then, if they perform poorly only in the former cases, he
should conclude that that difference also points to late-evening party-going as the likely
cause of their poor performance. In fact, although the methods of agreement and difference
are independent, they are usually employed jointly for the sake of greater precision.
The method of concomitant variation The method of concomitant variation rests on the
following principles:
1. When variations of one sort are highly correlated with variations of another, one is likely
to be the cause of the other, or they may both be caused by something else.
2. When variations in one phenomenon are highly correlated with variations in another
phenomenon, one of the two is likely to be the cause of the other, or they may both be
caused by some third factor.
Suppose now someone asks the coach why being fit matters for the members of a team. He
may safely invoke empirical evidence to argue that there is a causal relationship between a
player's being fit and his or her performance:
37 1. The more fit the players are, the better their performance.
2. Probably, being fit causes their better performance, or their better performance
causes their being fit, or something else causes both their better performance and
their being fit.
The underlying reasoning is roughly
38 1. X varies in a certain way if and only if Yvaries in a certain way.
2. Y causes X, or X causes Y, or some Z causes both X and Y.
Analogy
Analogy is a type of inductive argument whereby a certain conclusion about individuals,
qualities, or classes is drawn on the basis of some similarities with other individuals, qualities,
or classes. Here is an example of an analogy whose conclusion about a certain vehicle rests on
this vehicle having some things in common with other similar vehicles:
39 1. Mary's vehicle, a 2007 SUV, is expensive to run.
2. Jane's vehicle is a 2007 SUV and is expensive to run.
3. Simon's vehicle is a 2007 SUV and is expensive to run.
4. Peter's vehicle is a 2007 SUV.
5. Peter's vehicle is expensive to run.
In (39), the arguer attempts to make her conclusion reasonable by analogy: Peter's vehicle
shares two features with Mary's, Jane's, and Simon's: being a 2007 model and an SUV. This
provides some reason to think that it may also have in common a third feature, that of being
expensive to run. Let 'm,' 'j,' 's,' and 'p' stand, respectively, for Mary's vehicle, Jane's vehicle,
Simon's vehicle, and Peter's vehicle; and A, B, and C for the ascribed features: being a 2007
model, being an SUV, and being expensive to run. Then (39)'s pattern is
w
f--
0
🙂
0
z
LL
0
(j)
w
Q._
f- f
w z
2W
02
(j) 🙂
CJ
(\J a:
l
o
:::J
0
z
C)
z
N
<{
z
<{
39' 1. m is A, B, and C
2. j is A, B, and C
3. s is A, B, and C
4. pis A and B
5. p is C
Any argument along these lines would fall short of being deductive (i.e., of entailing its
conclusion). Yet if its premises are true, they might provide good evidence for it. Analogies can
make their conclusions plausible, provided that they meet the standards for good inductive
arguments discussed below. Among the specific factors that matter for the success of
analogies are those presented in Box 4.
Now consider
40 Extensive research on polar bears and hippos has shown that they have a great number
of relevant features in common with large animals that live in the wild. These animals
are also listed as endangered species. So polar bears and hippos might disappear.
The pattern of reasoning underlying this analogy is
1. Polar bears and hippos have a number of relevant things in common with species
x, y, and z.
2. Species x, y. and z also have feature f (being an endangered species).
3. Polar bears and hippos probably have feature f.
If polar bears and hippos do in fact share a number of features with threatened species, and
such features are truly relevant to the conclusion of this argument, then (40) can be said to
succeed in rendering its conclusion plausible.
BOX 4 ■ ANALOGY
Whether an analogy succeeds or not depends on
1. The number of things and the number of features held to be analogous.
■ Greater numbers here would make an analogy stronger.
2. The degree of similarities and dissimilarities among those things.
■ More of the former and less of the latter would make an analogy stronger.
3. The relevance of ascribed features to the hypothesis.
■ Greater relevance would make an analogy stronger.
4. The boldness of the hypothesis with respect to the evidence.
■ Modesty in the hypothesis would make an analogy stronger.
Exercises
1 . Discuss three features of inductive argument that distinguish them from deductive arguments.
2. What's the problem with asserting the premises of an inductive argument while denying its
conclusion?
3. Why are the premises and conclusion of an inductive argument called 'evidence' and 'hypothesis' ,
respectively?
4. What does it mean to say that a hypothesis is 'plausible'?
5. What is an enumerative induction?
6. What's the difference between universal and non-universal generalizations? How can a universal
generalization be proved false?
7. Describe the structure of a statistical syllogism.
8. Describe the structure of a causal argument.
9. Why is the word 'cause' ambiguous?
1 0. Describe the structure of an analogy.
II. Determine whether the following arguments are deductive or inductive.
1. Many whales observed in this region are white mammals. Therefore, any whale in this region is a
white mammal.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Inductive argument
2. Triangles have exactly three internal angles. Rectangles have exactly four internal angles. Therefore,
rectangles are not triangles.
*3. If all magnolias have a scent, then the magnolias in the vase have a scent. But they don't. It follows
that it isn't true that all magnolias have a scent.
4. Buying a house is a good investment. After all, that's exactly what statistics have shown for the last
ten years.
5. All samples of river water so far tested have been polluted. Thus all river water is polluted.
*6. The Crusades were bloody, for most medieval wars were bloody, and the Crusades were
medieval wars.
7. Surely the Earth is not flat. If it were flat, then Magellan could not have circumnavigated it. But he did!
8. Jane is a dentist and has clean teeth. Bruce is a dentist and has clean teeth. Therefore, all dentists
have clean teeth.
*9. Cars are mechanical devices. No mechanical devices are easy to fix. Thus no car is easy to fix.
10. Many medical doctors care about their patients. Tom is a medical doctor. Thus he cares about his
patients.
11. Mary doesn't like being denied a salary increase, for she is a state worker, and no state worker
likes that.
*12. To be an ophthalmologist is to be an eye specialist MD. My new neighbors are eye specialist MDs, so
they are ophthalmologists.
w
>
l
o
:::>
0
z
u..
0
(f)
w
0..
>-
1- 1-
w z
::’2′ w
0 ::’2′
(fJ :::>
(‘) N a:
(0 <1'.
(f)
�
z
w
2
:::>
(.’J
a:
e-
0
:::>
0
z
(.’J
z
N
r-
0
::)
0
z
0
z
��
::) z
….J w
;;�
w::)
C’) (9 . a::
co <(
IEilll
(j)
1-z w
�
::J
(_'; a:
�
w
>
l
o
::J
0
z
(_’;
z
N
�
� z
�
11111m
When an inductive argument is reliable, it has a form that makes its conclusion plausible
provided that its premises are true. Consider
41 1. 99 percent of guitar players also play other musical instruments.
2. Phong is a guitar player.
3. Phong also plays other musical instruments.
This inductive argument seems pretty reliable: its form is such that, if its premises were true,
its conclusion would be plausible. Compare (42), which is itself less reliable than (41) but more
reliable than (43):
42 1. 59 percent of guitar players also play other musical instruments.
2. Phong is a guitar player.
3. Phong also plays other musical instruments.
43 1. 39 percent of guitar players also play other musical instruments.
2. Phong is a guitar player.
3. Phong also plays other musical instruments.
Inductive reliability is, then, a matter of degree. An inductive argument of (44)’s form is more
reliable than (45):
44 1. 59 percent of A are B
2. p is an A
3. p is a B
45 1. 39 percent of A are B
2. p is an A
3. p is a B
The cash value of inductive reliability for logical thinkers can be better appreciated by comparing
it to the cash value of deductive validity. Each of these concerns argument form, as well as the sup
port an argument’s premises may give its conclusion, provided they are true. In the case of a valid
argument, if its premises are true, its conclusion must be true. In that of a reliable argument, if its
premises are true, its conclusion is likely to be true. As we saw in Chapter 5, a valid deductive
argument is truth-preserving. By contrast, a reliable inductive argument is not. Even so, inductive
reliability is one of the two desirable features that ordinary and scientific arguments should have.
Inductive Strength
Strength is another desirable feature for inductive arguments; thus we may use it to
evaluate such arguments. An inductive argument is strong just in case it meets the
conditions listed in Box 5.
BOX 5 ■ STRONG INDUCTIVE ARGUMENT
An inductive argument is strong if and only if
1. It is reliable.
2. It has all true premises.
When an inductive argument is strong, it is reasonable to accept its conclusion. That is, it
is reasonable to think that the conclusion is true. We may think of this standard in terms of
competition: given the structure of an inductive argument, rival conclusions are always
logically possible. Imagine a case where a professor in Biology 100 has just received an email
from one of her new students, whose name is Robin Mackenzie. She is trying to decide
whether she should begin her reply, ‘Dear Mr. Mackenzie’ or ‘Dear Ms. Mackenzie.’ Let’s
assume that it is true that 80 percent of the students in Biology 100 are women and reason
through the steps of this inductive argument:
46 1. 80 percent of the students in Biology 100 are women.
2. Robin is a student in Biology 100.
3. Robin is a woman.
Since (46) is an inductive argument, the conclusion, statement 3, may in fact fail to be true,
even if both premises are true. After all, a person named ‘Robin’ could be a man. Even so, given
the evidence provided by the premises, it seems that conclusion 3 is more plausible than the
other competing hypothesis (i.e., that Robin is a man). But imagine a different scenario:
suppose that we knew that 80 percent of the students in Biology 100 were men. Then, among
then the competing hypotheses, the conclusion that is most likely to be true on the basis of
that information is that Robin is a man. The argument now is
47 1. 80 percent of the students in Biology 100 are men.
2. Robin is a student in Biology 100.
3. Robin is a man.
We may alternatively define inductive strength in this way:
An inductive argument is strong if and only if its hypothesis is the one that has the greatest
probability of being true on the basis of the evidence.
In the same way that inductive reliability can be contrasted with deductive validity,
inductive strength can be contrasted with deductive soundness. For one thing, the latter does
not come in degrees, since it depends on validity and truth, neither of which is itself a matter
of degree (there’s no such thing as a ‘sort of true’ premise or a ‘sort of valid’ argument). Hence,
just as any given deductive argument is either valid or invalid, so, too, it’s either sound or
unsound. On the other hand, inductive strength does come in degrees, for it depends in part
on reliability, which is a matter of degree. What about the cash value of these standards? When
an argument is deductively sound, its conclusion is true-and must be accepted by any logical
thinker who recognizes the argument’s soundness. But the conclusion of any inductively
strong argument can be, at most, probably true-and thus reasonable to accept by a logical
w
>
l
o
:J
0
z
(9
z
i= en
<( 1-:J z
_J w
;; 2
w :J
C') (9 . a:
co <(
IIDII
(f)
1-
z
w
�
:::J
(')
a:
<(
w
>
i==
0
:::J
0
z
(‘)
z
N
<(
z
<(
111m
thinker who recognizes the argument's strength. For each of the two criteria by which we
assess inductive arguments, then, we may summarize its cash value as follows:
Inductive Reliability's Cash Value
■ If an argument has a good share of reliability, then it would be reasonable to accept
its conclusion, provided that its premises are true.
Inductive Strength's Cash Value
■ If an argument has a good share of inductive strength, then it's reasonable to accept
its conclusion, since it has a reliable form and its premises are true.
What, then, of inductive arguments that fail by one or the other of these two criteria? No such
argument could provide good reasons for their conclusions.
Exercises
1. What are the two standards for evaluating an inductive argument? Define each.
2. Does inductive reliability depend on the form of an argument? What about strength?
3. What question should we ask to determine whether an inductive argument is reliable?
4. Assuming that an inductive argument is reliable, when would it be strong?
5. Does the cash value of deductive validity differ from that of inductive reliability? Explain.
6. What factors are relevant to determining whether an enumerative induction is reliable?
7. What factors are relevant to determining whether an enumerative induction is strong or weak?
8. What factors are relevant to determining whether an analogy is reliable?
VII. Identify whether the arguments below are enumerative inductions, analogies,
causal arguments, or statistical syllogisms, and determine which are reliable and
which are not. For any argument whose reliability cannot be determined, explain
why not.
1. There is consensus among experts that heavy drinking is linked to liver disease. Therefore, heavy
drinking leads to liver disease.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Causal argument, reliable
2. Millions of fish so far observed have all been cold-blooded animals. Thus all fish are cold-blooded
animals.
*3. Most South American coffee beans are dark. Brazilian coffee beans are South American coffee
beans. Hence, Brazilian coffee beans are dark.
4. Nancy lives downtown and pays a high rent. Bob lives downtown and pays a high rent. Pam pays a
high rent. Thus Pam probably lives downtown.
5. 40 percent of college students sleep less than eight hours a day. Peter is a college student.
Therefore, Peter sleeps less than eight hours a day.
*6. Every pizza eater I have met liked mozzarella. Thus pizza eaters like mozzarella.
7. Betty's pet is carnivorous, and so are Lois's, Brenda's, and John's. It follows that all pets are
carnivorous.
8. Senegal is an African nation and has a forest. Nigeria is an African nation and has a forest. Since
Egypt is also an African nation, it probably has a forest.
*9. Caffeine is related to poor memory. All recent studies have shown that people can improve their
memory by reducing their daily consumption of caffeinated drinks.
10. Among families that have lived in Spring Valley for more than ten years, nearly 90 percent say they
like it there. My family will soon move to Spring Valley. So my family will like it there, too.
11. Since their discovery, microorganisms have been observed to be present in all infections. Thus
microorganisms are responsible for infections.
*12. Mike sells junk food, for he owns a fast-food restaurant, and that's what most fast-food
restaurants sell.
13. Frank Sinatra sang in a 1950s movie wearing a tuxedo. Sammy Davis Jr., Peter Lawford, and Joey
Bishop were all in tuxedos in that movie with Frank, and they made up 90 percent of the male actors
cast in it. Since Dean Martin also sang in the same movie, he must have worn a tuxedo.
14. From 1951 to 2001, Sir Richard Doll documented the mortality rate of British male doctors born
between 1900 and 1930. 81 percent of nonsmokers lived to at least age seventy, but only
58 percent of smokers lived to that age. Cigarette smoking stood out in Doll's findings as the only
major factor distinguishing these two groups of doctors. Thus the shorter survival rate in the second
group was a result of smoking.
*15. Chase is a bank and makes home-finance loans. Citibank is a bank and makes home-finance loans.
Wells Fargo is a bank and also makes home-finance loans. This suggests that all U.S. banks make
home finance loans.
16. After an extensive study involving major research universities, scientists discovered that poison ivy
grew there at 2.5 times its normal rate when they pumped carbon dioxide through pipes into a pine
forest. Their work suggests that atmospheric carbon dioxide is at least partially responsible for the
higher growth rate of poison ivy.
17. I' ll be accepted. Let's not forget that 98 percent of applicants with my qualifications get accepted.
*18. Given that T ina Turner is a famous singer and has an insurance policy on her legs, Queen Latifah
probably has one, too. After all, she is also a famous singer.
19. 92 percent of computer owners cannot get through a typical day without using their computers. John
is a computer owner; thus he probably cannot get through a typical day without using his computer.
20. It'll cool off soon, for these winds from the northeast are bringing a cool front.
*21. Wood can be made to rot by breaking down lignin, the compound that holds plant tissue together.
This is in fact what fungus does to lignin. It has been proved that the molecular structure of lignin and
construction glues is similar. Therefore, fungus can be used to break construction glues.
w
>
l
o
::i
0
z
(‘.)
z
��
::i z
_J w
;; �
w ::i
(“) (‘.) . a:
co <(
(/)
f
z
w
:;;;
:::,
(.')
er
f-
0
:::,
0
z
(.’)
z
N
a:
<(
�
�
🙂
(/)
a:
w
f
Q_
<(
I
0
(J)
f
z
w
�
:::::,
C)
0::
�
0
:::::,
0
z
C)
z
N
�
–
CJ
a:
<(
z
<(
(/)
>–
<( _.J
3�
W LL
�z
0 <(
(/) 0
111111
7 .3 When Inductive Arguments Go Wrong
In this chapter, we consider five informal fallacies associated with the misuse of inductive
reasoning, grouped as follows:
BOX 2 ■ FALLACIES OF FAILED INDUCTION
FALLACIES OF
FAILED
INDUCTION
I I I j
APPEAL TO
APPEAL TO
HASTY WEAK FALSE
UNQUALIFIED
GENERALIZATION ANALOGY CAUSE IGNORANCE
AUTHORITY
I
POST Hoc ERGO
11
NON CAUSA 0vERSIMPLIFIED
I PROPTER Hoc PRO CAUSA CAUSE
Hasty Generalization
The fallacy of hasty generalization may affect enumerative induction. Earlier we saw that an
enumerative induction typically starts out with premises asserting that certain things have
(or lack) some feature, and then draws a general conclusion about all things of that kind, to the
effect that they have (or lack) that feature. The conclusion of the argument is a universal gener
alization, such as 'All leopards are carnivorous' and 'No leopard is carnivorous'. Thus an
enumerative induction might go like this:
1 1. All leopards so far observed have been carnivorous
2. All leopards are carnivorous
When a representative sample of leopards has been observed to be carnivorous, the conclusion
of this inductive argument is well supported. Similarly, if we've observed a representative
sample of leopards and found them all to be wild animals, we would be justified in drawing
the general conclusion that leopards are wild animals on the basis of those observations. Our
inductive argument would be,
2 1. Every leopard observed so far has been a wild animal
2. All leopards are wild animals
But for any such inductive conclusion to be justified, the conditions listed in Box 3 must be
met. If either of those two conditions, or both, is unfulfilled, then the argument commits
the fallacy of hasty generalization and therefore fails.
Hasty generalization is the mistake of trying to draw a conclusion about all things of a certain
kind having a certain feature on the basis of having observed too small a sample of the things
that allegedly have it, or a sample that is neither comprehensive nor randomly selected.
Suppose a team of naturalists were to observe 500,000 leopards, which all turn out to be
wild animals. Yet they were all observed in India, during the first week of August, at a time
when these animals were about to eat. The sample seems large enough, and the observers
might therefore draw the conclusion that
3 All leopards are wild animals.
But they would be committing a hasty generalization, since leopards are also found in other parts
of the world. And they are found at other times of the year, and in other situations. Clearly, the
sample lacks comprehensiveness and randomness. In this case, argument (2) would fail to provide
a good reason for its conclusion. On the other hand, suppose the naturalists directly observed
patterns of wild behavior among leopards in all parts of the world where such animals are found,
at different times of the year, and in many different situations. Yet the sample now consists of
only thirty-seven leopards. Do the naturalists have better grounds for concluding (3) above? No,
because although the comprehensiveness and randomness criteria are now met, the sample is
too small. The charge of hasty generalization would similarly apply in this scenario.
It is, however, not only naturalists and other scientists who will need to beware of this
sort of blunder. Logical thinkers will want to be on guard for hasty generalization in many
everyday situations. Among these is the familiar mistake of stereotyping people. Suppose
someone from the Midwest visits California for the first time. He becomes acquainted with
three native Californians, and it happens that all three practice yoga. Imagine that, on his
return home after his vacation, he tells his friends,
4 All Californians practice yoga.
If challenged, he would offer this argument:
5 1. I met Margaret Evans, who is Californian and practices yoga.
2. I met Alisa Mendoza, who is Californian and practices yoga.
3. I met Michael Yoshikawa, who is Californian and practices yoga.
4. All Californians practice yoga.
The reasoning in (s) is again an instance of hasty generalization. Furthermore, it stereotypes
Californians: on the basis of the sample described by the premises, the conclusion is simply
unwarranted.
Now imagine a different scenario: suppose that an anthropologist visited California with the
intention of studying the folkways of modern Californians. Suppose she went to southern
California, northern California, the San Joaquin Valley, the Bay Area, all regions of the state, and
met Californians from all walks of life, all social groups, all religions, all ethnic groups-from
cities, suburbs, small towns, and rural areas. Suppose she talked to thousands, and suppose she
discovered that all of these people practiced yoga! (This is unlikely, but suppose it happened.)
Then it would not be a fallacy to draw conclusion 4: assuming the thoroughness and breadth of
the study, this conclusion would be a reasonable outcome of a strong enumerative induction.
0
(!)
(f) 1-z w
�
:::i
(!) a:
l
o
:::i
0
z
z w (!)
I z
s: 0
C’) a:
….: s:
1-
z
LU
2
:::i
CJ
a:
f–
0
::)
0
z
z w (‘)
I z
s: 0
C’) a:
r-..: s:
IHN
t
z
UJ
�
:J
CJ
a:
<{
z
<{
(/)
>–
<{ ...J
3�
UJ LL
�z
0 <{
(/) 0
infer that she caught the chicken pox from her sisters. Given what we know about how
infectious diseases are transmitted, this inductive conclusion seems supported. But not all
causal arguments are strong. When either of the two types of error listed in Box s occurs, a
fallacy of false cause has been committed.
False cause is the mistake of arguing that there is a significant causal connection between
two phenomena, when in fact the connection is either minimal or nonexistent.
BOX 5 ■ HOW TO AVOID THE FALLACY OF FALSE CAUSE
Causal arguments can fail in two basic ways:
■ The argument concludes that there is a cause-effect connection between two phenomena
where there is none at all.
■ The argument mistakenly identifies some phenomenon as a sufficient (or determining) cause,
when in fact it's only a contributory cause (i.e., one among many) of some observed effect.
Let's consider three different ways the fallacy of false cause may occur. One is:
Post hoc ergo propter hoc ('after this, therefore because of this'):
The fallacy of concluding that some earlier event is the cause of some later event, when
the two are in fact not causally related.
The inclination to commit this fallacy in everyday life rests on the fact that, when we see two
events constantly conjoined-so that they are always observed to occur together, first the one,
then the other-it may eventually seem natural to assume that the earlier is the cause of the latter.
But it is not difficult to imagine cases of precisely this sort where an imputation of causal connec
tion would be absurd. Suppose we saw a bus passing the courthouse in the square just before the
clock in the tower struck 9:00 a.m., and we then continued to see the exact same sequence of
events day after day. Do we at last want to say that it's the bus's passing the courthouse that causes
the clock to strike 9:00 a.m.? Of course not! And yet, in our experience, the two events have been
constantly conjoined: the clock's striking has always been preceded by the bus's passing.
Clearly it would be preposterous to argue, in that case, that, from the evidence of constant
conjunction between the bus's passing and the clock's striking 9:00, it follows that the former
causes the latter. But equally absurd arguments are in fact sometimes heard in everyday life.
Suppose that Hector and Barbara are not getting along, and one of their friends ventures to
explain the source of the problem:
8 1. Hector was born under the sign of Capricorn.
2. Barbara was born under Pisces.
3. Capricorns and Pisces are not compatible.
4. Their recent difficulties are owing to their having incompatible zodiac signs.
Argument (8) fails to support its conclusion, since it claims a causal connection for which the
argument gives no good evidence-nor, in this case, should we expect good evidence to be
forthcoming. After all, there's no good reason to think that configurations of stars and other
celestial events really do affect the courses of our lives, and whatever the cause of this couple's
troubles may be, it's probably traceable to something else. Argument (8) is a fallacy of post hoc
ergo propter hoc, a form of false cause, for it assumes a cause-effect relation between being born
on a day when celestial bodies have a certain configuration (which determines a certain zodiac
sign) and subsequently growing up to develop certain personality traits. But there is no reason
to think that these two sequential events are in fact causally related.
Another way false cause may occur is
Non causa pro causa (roughly, what is not the cause is mistaken for the cause):
A fallacy in which the error is not an imputation of causality in a temporal sequence of
events (as in post hoc ergo propter hoc, where an earlier event is wrongly thought to be
the cause of a later one), but rather the simple mistake of misidentifying some event
contemporaneous with another as its cause, when in reality it's not.
One form of this error occurs when cause and effect are confused. An early nineteenth-century
study of British agriculture noted that, of farmers surveyed, all the hard-working and industri
ous ones owned at least one cow, while all the lazy ones owned no cows. This led the
researchers to conclude that productivity could be improved overall and habits of industry
encouraged in the lazy farmers by simply giving them each of those farmers a cow!
Now, plainly there is something wrong in this reasoning. But what? It seems to rest on an
extended argument along these lines:
9 1. All of the observed industrious farmers are cow owners.
2. None of the observed lazy farmers is a cow owner.
3. All and only cow-owning farmers are industrious.
4. There is a positive correlation between cow-owning and industriousness.
5. It's cow-owning that causes industrious farmers to be industrious.
If we grant, for the sake of discussion, that the sample of British farmers in the study was large
enough, and that it was also comprehensive and randomly selected, then premises 1 and 2
support conclusion 3, and its restatement, conclusion 4. But s's claim about cause and effect
fails to be supported! It's industriousness that is probably the cause of cow-owning, and not the
other way around. By confusing cause with effect, (9) commits non causa pro causa.
Finally, there is a version of false cause in which the source of the mistake is something
rather different from what we've seen so far:
Oversimplified cause:
The fallacy of overstating the causal connection between two events that do have some
causal link.
0
(.')
(/)
f
z
w
�
:::,
(.')
0:
–
<( __J
� <(
LlJ u..
�z
0 <(
(/) 0
Suppose a vice president, campaigning for reelection, says,
10 1. At the beginning of this administration's term, the national economy was sluggish.
2. At the end of this administration's term, the national economy is booming.
3. White House economic policies do have an effect on the nation's economy.
4. The improvement in the economy is due to this administration's policies.
(10) fails to support its conclusion. Let's assume that the premises are true. Even then, the
causal relation asserted in premise 3 is merely one of contributory cause-in effect, one causal
factor among others-which amounts to a rather weak sense of 'cause.' But 4 grandly asserts as
the conclusion something much more than that: namely, that the actions taken by the incum
bent administration are a sufficient cause of the improvement in the economy. Now, surely
this is an exaggeration. The campaigning vice president commits a fallacy of oversimplified
cause by taking full credit for the nation's economic turnaround, thereby overstating the sense
in which his administration's policies 'caused' it. Of course, many politicians are quite prepared
to take credit for anything good that happens while they're in office. But proving that it was
due entirely to their efforts is something else again. The logical thinker should be on guard for
this and any of the other versions of false cause as representing different ways in which a
causal argument may fail.
BOX 6 ■ THREE TYPES OF CAUSAL FALLACY
Post Hoc Ergo
Propter Hoc
Appeal to Ignorance
FALLACY OF FALSE
CAUSE
Non Causa Pro
Causa
Oversimplified
Cause
Another fallacy of failed induction is the appeal to ignorance (or ad ignorantiam): an argu
ment that commits this fallacy concludes either that some statement is true because it has
never been proved false, or that it is false because it has never been proved true. More
generally,
The fallacy of appeal to ignorance is committed by any argument in which the conclusion
that something is (or isn't) the case is supposedly supported by appeal to the lack of
evidence to the contrary.
Suppose someone reasons,
11 1. It has never been proved that God doesn't exist.
2. We can confidently assert that God exists.
(11) commits the fallacy of appeal to ignorance, but so does (12):
12 1. It has never been proved that God exists.
2. We can confidently assert that God doesn't exist.
Similarly, a believer in 'extrasensory perception' might argue,
13 1. No one has ever been able to prove that ESP doesn't exist.
2. It's reasonable to believe that there is ESP.
Clearly, the only reason offered by (13) to support its conclusion is the absence of contrary evi
dence. But from that premise, all that can be supported is that we don't know what to say about
ESP! The conclusion given-that "it's reasonable to believe that there is ESP"-is far too strong
to be supported by such a flimsy premise. Reasoning along similar lines could also be used to
demonstrate the failure of (11) and (12).
BOX 7 ■ HOW TO AVOID THE FALLACY OF APPEAL
TO IGNORANCE
■ An argument whose premises merely invoke the lack of evidence against a certain conclusion
commits the fallacy of appeal to ignorance. Such premises are bad reasons for the conclusion
they attempt to support, and the argument therefore fails.
■ Why? Because the mere lack of negative evidence does not in itself constitute positive evidence
for anything! It justifies nothing more than an attitude of non belief (i.e., neutrality) toward
the conclusion.
We must, however, add a note of caution. Suppose that the attempt to prove some claim
has occasioned rigorous scientific investigation, and that these efforts have repeatedly turned
up no evidence in support of the claim. Furthermore, suppose that the claim doesn't serve the
purpose of explaining anything. In that case, it is not a fallacy to reject that claim out of hand.
Here we have to proceed case by case. Consider the claim,
14 There are witches.
Although there is of course a long history of claims that witches exist, all efforts to prove those
claims have so far failed for lack of evidence. Furthermore, the concept of a witch has no serious
explanatory function in any scientific theory: the existence of witches doesn't explain anything that
happens in the natural world. These considerations suggest that it is not a fallacy to conclude,
15 Probably there are no witches.
Inductive conclusions of this sort are rendered plausible by the absence of reliable empirical
evidence after thorough investigation, and must not be confused with the fallacy of appeal to
ignorance.
0
C)
f-
0
:::i
0
z
z
w CJ
Iz
s: 0
(“) rr:
r–: s:
f
z
L!J
2
🙂
0
a:
l
o
::J
0
z
w (.9
I z
3: 0 (“) er:
,-..: 3:
1-
z
w
�
:::J
(!)
er:
<(
z
<(
(f)
>–
<( _J
� ;j:
W LL
�z
0 <(
(f) ()
Argument (19) appeals to the view of experts on the topic of the conclusion, which is
supported-provided that the premise is true. Since an appeal to authority is often needed for
the justification of many claims, it is crucial that we distinguish between legitimate authorities
who have expertise relevant to the claim being made and those who don't. The rule is:
In evaluating an argument of the form, A says P, therefore P, check whether A is a
genuine authority expressing a view on P that is well represented among the experts on
P. If A is not, then the argument fails to support its conclusion and must be rejected.
For example, beliefs about history are more reasonable when based on the writings of
reputable professional historians than when proposed by amateur ones. If we want to have
well-founded beliefs about the French Revolution, the Ming Dynasty, or the presidency of
Theodore Roosevelt, we should look to writers whose books are not "self-published" or
published by vanity presses (where the authors pay to get their books into print). We should
look for historians who are held in high regard by peers in their fields and whose work has
been favorably reviewed. Although none of these criteria guarantee expertise, they make it
vastly more likely. Similarly, for beliefs about nature, it goes without saying that respected
journals in the natural sciences are generally dependable sources of information, unlike
supermarket tabloids that describe miracle cures for cancer and 'evidence' of mental telepathy.
For scientists, too, being the author of respected, mainstream scholarship and having the
favorable regard of fellow scholars are usually the marks of credibility as genuine experts. For
logical thinkers, then, an important competence is the ability to tell the difference between
real experts and bogus ones, since it is often on that distinction that the difference between
legitimate appeals to authority and the fallacy of appeal to unqualified authority turns.
BOX 9 ■ HOW TO AVOID FALLACIOUS APPEALS TO
AUTHORITY
To avoid fallacious appeal to authority, keep in mind the way it differs from appeals to authority
that aren't fallacious. The difference hinges on whether the authority cited in support of a claim
■ does indeed have sufficient expertise in the relevant field; and
■ is expressing a view well represented (perhaps the prevailing one) among experts on the topic.
Exercises
1 . What is a fallacy?
2. What's the point of studying fallacies, as far as logical thinking is concerned?
3. What is the fallacy of hasty generalization?
4. Are all generalizations to be avoided?
5. What is stereotyping? And how is this related to hasty generalization?
6. What is the fallacy of weak analogy?
7. The fallacy of false cause has at least three different forms. Identify the kind of mistake each makes,
and explain why they are all mistakes in causal reasoning.
8. What is the fallacy of appeal to ignorance?
9. When a fallacy of appeal to unqualified authority is committed, who commits it? Is it the arguer or
the bogus authority?
1 o. What is the difference between the legitimate use of appeal to authority and the fallacy of appeal to
unqualified authority?
II. Each of the following arguments commits one of the fallacies of failed induction
discussed in this chapter. Identify the fallacy.
1. I'm an Aquarius, so I love doing lots of projects at once.
SAMPLE ANSWER: False cause
2. Some people can cure heart disease by meditation. I know because the coach of my son's soccer
team told me.
*3. Wage and price controls will not work as a means of controlling the rate of inflation. After all, no econ
omist has ever been able to give conclusive proof that such controls are effective against inflation.
4. Most HIV patients are young. Thus youth causes HIV.
5. Yogi Berra, an Italian American, was one of the greatest baseball players of all time. Other all-time
greats of baseball include Joe DiMaggio, Mike Piazza, and Roy Campanella. So, no doubt about it,
Italian Americans are great baseball players.
*6. Last week, when Notre Dame won the game, the coach was wearing his green tie. So their victory
must have been due to the coach's choice of necktie, since this nearly always happens when he
wears that tie.
*7. Foreign wars are good for a nation, just as exercise is good for the body. In the same way that
exercise keeps the body fit, foreign wars keep a nation fit as a society.
8. According to recent polls of registered voters, the state of Massachusetts has a large percentage of
voters who are political liberals. This suggests that all states have a large percentage of voters who
are political liberals.
*9. The chances for stability in the Middle East will continue to improve. Popular singer Britney Spears
has recently said that that is what she expects to happen.
10. Dallas and Houston are North American cities, and one can drive from the one to the other in only a
few hours. Montreal and Los Angeles are also North American cities. Thus one can drive from
Montreal to Los Angeles in only a few hours.
11. Some years ago, after not having seen my best friend from Duckwood High School for several years,
we met for lunch and were surprised to find that our clothes and hairstyles were the same! The only
possible explanation for this is that we both went to Duckwood High.
*12. Some regular churchgoers believe that taxpayers' dollars should not be used to fund laboratories
that carry out tests on animals for medical research. Hence, it is wrong to go on spending taxpayers'
dollars for that purpose.
f-
z
w
w
f-
z
z
w 0
I z
so
C') a:
r--: s
1-
z
w
�
:::i
('J
a:
f-
0
:::J
0
z
w C)
Iz
so
C’) a:
r–: s
111111
1-
z
w
2
::i
CJ
a:
<(
z
<(
C/)
>–
<( .J
� <(
W LL
2 z
0 <(
C/) 0
-
*5. The Secretary of Defense sees signs of growth in our economy. Thus our economy is recovering.
6. The universe can act as a magnifying lens. One of the best current physical theories, Einstein's, says so.
*7. It is simply false that cell-phone use creates the risk of developing a brain tumor. Five well-established
cell-phone companies surveyed this issue extensively, all reaching the same conclusion: no such risk
exists. More details on this are available at the companies' web pages.
8. There is nothing wrong with drinking coffee. Many U.S. presidents, including Theodore Roosevelt,
are known to have been coffee drinkers.
*9. Although much can be said against diets low in carbohydrates, one thing is decisive: calories from
carbohydrates enhance cognitive tasks. After all, that's the shared view among leading nutritionists.
10. Kids should avoid riding in school buses. This conclusion is supported by the remarks of the treasurer
of the Parents' Association at the last meeting at Emerson School, who noted that the exhaust gases
produced by diesel vehicles harm the children's respiratory systems.
VI. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
For each the following arguments, first identify the fallacy that it might commit, and then provide premises
or a scenario where it does not commit that fallacy.
*1. Every tiger so far observed has been fearless. Therefore, all tigers are fearless.
2. My mother and her circle of friends think that species have evolved. Therefore, species have evolved.
*3. Nobody has ever observed a centaur. Therefore, centaurs do not exist.
4. Ellen and Jose are both college students who vote. Both are also pre-law majors. Jose is also
interested in golf. Therefore, Ellen is interested in golf.
■ Writing Project
The language of the media makes frequent use of analogy. Go to the web and Google three
articles containing analogies on topics such as 'Saddam and Hitler,' 'Vietnam and
Afghanistan,' and 'Recession and the Great Depression' or another analogy of your choice (be
sure to check with your instructor on that). Select and summarize the arguments in three of
the articles. Use your summaries to write a short essay (about two double-spaced pages)
discussing whether the analogies in each are strong or weak analogies. If weak, explain why
the analogy fails. Otherwise, explain why you think it should be allowed to stand.
■ Chapter Summary
Fallacy: in the case of argument, a pattern of failed relation between premises and conclusion.
It could be:
1. A formal fallacy, which is a type of mistake made by arguments that may appear to be
instances of a valid argument form but are in fact invalid in virtue of their form.
2. An informal fallacy, which is a pattern of failed relation between the premises and
conclusion of an argument owing to some defect in expression or content.
BOX 10 ■ INFORMAL FALLACIES
I
INFORMAL
I FALLACIES
I I I I
Fallacies of Failed Fallacies of Fallacies of Fallacies of
Induction Presumption Unclear Language Relevance
Hasty generalization: Committed by any enumerative induction whose conclusion
rests on a sample that is either too small or lacking in comprehensiveness and
randomness, or both. Stereotyping people is one form of hasty generalization.
Weak analogy: Committed by any analogy in which the things alleged to be alike are
in fact not very much alike in relevant ways. Not all arguments from analogy are
fallacious.
False cause: The mistake of concluding that there is a significant causal connection
between two events, when in fact there is either a minimal causal connection or none
at all. Not all causal arguments are fallacious.
Appeal to ignorance: Committed by any argument whose conclusion rests on noth
ing more than the absence of evidence to the contrary.
Appeal to unqualified authority: Committed by any argument in which the conclu
sion is supposedly supported by the say-so of some "authority" who is not really an
expert in the relevant field or whose position is at odds with the prevailing consensus
of expert opinion. Not all appeals to authority are fallacious.
■ Key Words
Fallacy
Informal fallacy
Weak analogy
False cause
Appeal to ignorance
Appeal to unqualified authority
Post hoc ergo propter hoc
Oversimplified cause
Non causa pro causa
Hasty generalization
(f)
0
a:
0
3:
>
w
�
ID
CHAPTER
Avoiding Ungrounded
Assumptions
In this chapter you’ll learn about the fallacies of presumption and some related
logical and philosophical issues. The topics include
■ Circular reasoning: When is it vicious? When is it benign?
■ The fallacies of begging the question and begging the question against.
The concept of burden of proof.
■ The fallacy of complex question.
■ The fallacy of false alternatives.
■ The fallacy of accident.
166
8.1 Fallacies of Presumption
Now we’re ready to look at some fallacies that can be grouped together because arguments
committing them take for granted something that is in fact debatable. Such arguments rest on
presumptions, which are strong assumptions or background beliefs taken for granted.
Generally, there is nothing wrong with presumptions: arguments commonly rest on implicit
beliefs that create no fallacy of presumption at all. But when an argument takes for granted a
belief that is in fact debatable, it commits a fallacy of presumption. The unsupported belief at
work in such fallacious arguments may at first seem innocent or even acceptable, though in
reality it is neither. The patterns of mistake illustrated by arguments that rest on debatable
presumptions include the five types of fallacy listed in Box 1.
BOX 1 ■ SOME FALLACIES OF PRESUMPTION
I FALLACIES OF I PRESUMPTION
BEGGING THE BEGGING THE
I
COMPLEX
I
FALSE I ACCIDENT I QUESTION QUESTION QUESTION ALTERNATIVES
AGAINST
8.2 Begging the Question
In Chapter s we saw that the premises of valid arguments could be true yet fall short of count
ing as persuasive reasons for their conclusion. That would be the case with any sound argument
that failed to be cogent. As a result, no such argument can move a rational thinker to accept its
conclusion, even when the validity of the argument may be obvious to the thinker. Why?
Imagine that we intend to convince you rationally to accept a certain claim-say, that
1 We care about logical thinking.
We offer you this reason as a premise:
2 It is not the case that we don’t care about logical thinking.
The argument is
3 1. It is not the case that we don’t care about logical thinking.
2. We care about logical thinking.
(3) is valid, and we may assume that it has a true premise. Yet it lacks cogency, since it doesn’t
offer reasons that could persuade a logical thinker of the truth of its conclusion if that thinker
is skeptical about that very conclusion. Philosophers call this ‘circular reasoning.’ (3) is affected
by a degree of circularity that may be considered ‘vicious,’ since it would make any argument
that has it fail-by contrast with ‘benign circularity,’ which, as we’ll see, is the tolerable degree
of circularity that affects many deductive arguments.
z
0
f
(f)
w
::J
a
w
I
f-
C)
z
C)
C)
w
m
N
00
0 LU
0
z
::,
0
a:
0 (J)
zz
::, 0
0 1-
z 0…
– �
e ::i
0 (J)
> (J)
<( <(
-
As just noted, any valid argument has some degree of circularity, due either to its form,
the concepts involved, or both. The following two arguments are affected by circularity
hinging on argument form:
8 1. Today it's cloudy and breezy.
2. Today it's breezy.
9 1. The Pope is in Rome.
2. The Pope is in Rome.
Clearly, the circularity afflicting these arguments hinges on their forms-which are
8 1. C and B
2. B
9 1. E
2. E
Any argument with either of these forms is valid, for if its premise is true, then its conclusion must
also be. But in each case the premise is not more acceptable than the conclusion it attempts to
support. As a result, no one could come to accept the conclusion on the basis of having worked out
the validity of the argument and found the premise acceptable.
Yet circularity may also be conceptual, hinging on the meaning or concepts involved.
Consider
10 1. If Kobe Bryant is a basketball player, then he plays basketball.
2. Kobe Bryant is a basketball player.
3. Kobe Bryant plays basketball.
11 1. Marianne was once abducted by alien beings from outer space.
2. There are alien beings from outer space.
In each argument, the premises presuppose the conclusion they are supposed to support, given
the concepts involved. In (10), no logical thinker who doubts that Kobe Bryant plays basketball
could come to accept that on the basis of the argument's premises. In (11), no logical thinker
who doubts the existence of alien beings from outer space could be persuaded that there are
such beings by the argument's premise. Each argument begs the question, thereby failing to be
cogent. As in (8) and (9) above, these arguments too are affected by circularity that renders
them fallacious. Whether formal or conceptual, circularity comes in degrees: too much of it
causes an argument to beg the question.
Benign Circularity
But circularity does not always make an argument question-begging. Compare
1 2 1. If the mind is the brain, then the mind is organic matter.
2. If the mind is organic matter, then it perishes with the body.
3. If the mind is the brain, then it perishes with the body.
BOX 3 ■ FORMAL AND CONCEPTUAL CIRCULARITY
Two TYPES OF
CIRCULARITY
Here the argument form is
12' 1. If M, then 0
2. If 0, then B
3. If M, then B
Formal
It hinges on
argument form
Conceptual
It hinges on
concepts involved
In an argument with this form, there is some formal circularity, since the propositions
represented as M and B appear not only in the conclusion, but also in the premises. Yet (12)
does not beg the question, because finding its premises acceptable and recognizing the
argument's validity could provide reasons to move logical thinkers to accept its conclusion.
Anyone who accepts the argument's premises and works out the entailment thereby
possesses a compelling reason to accept its conclusion. By contrast with viciously circular
arguments, coming to accept (12)'s conclusion on the basis of its premises amounts to a
cognitive achievement.
Let's now compare some conceptually circular arguments such as
13 1. Salsa is music for dancers.
2. Salsa is music for those who dance.
14 1. Andrew is a bachelor.
2. Andrew is unmarried.
15 1. She has drawn an isosceles triangle.
2. She has drawn a triangle.
All three of these arguments are valid: if their premises are true, their conclusions must be
true, as well. Yet under ordinary circumstances, each begs the question, for in each case
acceptance of its premise requires a previous acceptance of the conclusion. No logical thinker
who disputed the conclusion could be compelled to accept it on the basis of the argument's
premise and recognition of the argument's validity. But consider
16 1. The Moon orbits the Earth.
2. The Moon is a large celestial body.
3. Any large celestial body that orbits a planet is a satellite.
4. The Moon is a satellite.
z
0
1-
(/)
w
:::J
a
w
I
1-
(')
z
(')
(')
w
OJ
N
00
0
IJj
0
z
::::)
0
a:
CJ (/)
zz
::::) 0
CJ i=
z 0..
- �
e ::::i
0 (/)
> (/)
<( <(
Although in (16) there is some conceptual circularity between the concepts 'satellite' and 'large
celestial body that orbits a planet,' this does not make the argument question-begging. For a
logical thinker who lacked some basic astronomical knowledge and initially doubted claim 4
could be persuaded to accept it on the basis of deducing it from 1, 2, and 3, provided that she
were led to recognize the acceptability of those premises and the validity of the argument.
An important point to keep in mind is that
Logical circularity, whether formal or conceptual, comes in degrees. Some valid arguments
have more circularity than others. The more logically circular an argument is, the more its
conclusion follows trivially from its premises and is likely to beg the question.
The Burden of Proof
It is not uncommon to find the expression 'burden of proof' in dialectical contexts, which are
situations involving deliberation among two or more parties, such as a debate, controversy, or
deliberation on a disputed question between opposing sides defending incompatible claims.
'Burden of proof' refers to the obligation to take a turn in offering reasons, which, at any given
stage of the deliberation, is on one side or the other (except for the paradoxical situations
discussed below). A deliberation commonly follows this pattern: one party, C, makes a claim.
The other party, 0, replies by raising some objections to it. If these objections are adequate,
the burden of proof is now on C, who must get rid of (or 'discharge') it by offering reasons for
her claim. If she comes up with a sound or strong argument that outweighs O's argument, the
burden of proof then switches to 0, who must try to discharge it by offering the appropriate
arguments.
It may happen, however, that the reasons on both sides appear equally strong. As a result,
there would then be a dialectical impasse, or standoff in the deliberation. No progress can be
made until new reasons are offered to resolve the conflict. Except for these situations,
however, we may expect that the burden of proof will, at any given stage of a deliberation, be
on either the one side or the other. As the deliberation progresses, it will likely switch from the
one side to the other more than once, always falling on the participant whose claim is more in
need of support.
BOX 4 ■ WHERE IS THE BURDEN OF PROOF?
In the following debate,® shows the burden of proof andQan impasse.
1. A rejects a claim made by!!, which is a commonly held belie£®A
2. A defends her rejection with an argument that begs the question against!!-® A
3. A recasts her argument so that it now seems cogent.®!!
4. !! offers an argument that turns out to be clearly invalid.®!!
5. !!'s argument is modified and now seems as cogent as A's.Q
6. A provides further strong evidence in support of her view.®!!
7. !! replies by offering weak evidence for his view.®!!
8. !! offers further evidence which is equally strong as A's.Q
Commonsense beliefs, which are ordinary beliefs based on observation, memory, and
inference, enjoy a privileged standing with respect to the burden of proof. Whoever
challenges them has, at least initially, the burden of proof. For example, the belief that the
Earth has existed for more than five minutes belongs to common sense. If someone
challenges it, the burden of proof is on the challenger, who must now offer adequate
reasons against that commonsense belief. But that advantage can be overridden by a strong
argument if available.
Knowing where the burden of proof is at any given stage of a debate has this cash value:
■ If you know that the burden of proof is on you, you know you must discharge it by
offering an adequate argument in support of your claim.
■ If you know that the burden of proof is on the other side, you can rest until a sound
objection to your view has been offered.
■ If you know that you are defending a claim that is part of common sense, then you also
know that the burden of proof is on any challenger.
Finally, note that some deliberation goes on 'internally'-for example, when a person
reflects upon which of two opposite theories is correct. If, in the course of inner delibera
tion, a thinker is fair-minded, then the burden of proof will tend to shift from one position
she is considering to an opposite view, following the same general considerations outlined
above.
BOX 5 ■ RATIONAL DELIBERATION
EITHER ON ONE SIDE
THE BURDEN OF
PROOF IS
ON THE OTHER
SIDE, OR
8.3 Begging the Question Against
THERE IS AN IMPASSE
A common mistake that undermines argument is committed by failing to discharge the
burden of proof. Suppose that we assert 'Not P' (i.e., that Pis false), but someone else, Melinda,
has just offered us some good reason for thinking that P is true.
BOX 6 ■ HOW TO AVOID BEGGING THE QUESTION AGAINST
Don't include any controversial statement among your premises without first offering adequate
reasons for it.
I
(/)
z
<(
(')
<(
z
0
I
(/)
LiJ
=i
a
LiJ
I
I-
(')
z
(')
(')
LiJ
(l]
"'.
co
11111
0
UJ
0
z
:::)
0
0:
0 (f)
zz
:::) 0
0 f'.=
z a.
-�
e ::::i
0 (f)
> (f) <( <(
The burden of proof is now on us, and we must discharge it by offering an adequate
argument against P. The failure to do so-by assuming that P is false, without offering a reason
for this-commits the fallacy of begging the question against Melinda. For it amounts to
implicitly reasoning in either of these viciously circular forms:
17 1. P is false
2. P is false
Or similarly,
18 1. NotP
2. Not P
The fallacy of begging the question against (your opponent) is often committed in everyday
arguments on controversial topics. For example, when someone maintains
19 1. In abortion, the fetus is intentionally killed.
2. A fetus is an innocent person.
3. Intentionally killing an innocent person is always murder.
4. Abortion is always murder.
Although 1 seems unobjectionable, 2 and 3 are controversial premises that cannot be
employed unless good reasons have already been offered to back them up. Premise 2 begs
the question against the view that a fetus is not a person-a view that can be supported in a
number of ways (as most parties to the current popular debate over the morality of abortion
now recognize).
Begging the question against can be difficult to detect, for it involves presupposing the
truth of premises that, although controversial, are sometimes inadvertently taken for granted.
To avoid this fallacy, always abide by the rule in Box 6 above.
BOX 7 ■ SECTION SUMMARY
1. When an argument begs the question, at least one premise assumes the conclusion being
argued for.
2. When an argument begs the question against, at least one premise assumes something that
is in need of support.
Exercises
1 . What do all fallacies of presumption have in common?
2. What does it mean for an argument to be 'circular'? Is all circularity bad?
2. Define non-cogency in relation to begging the question.
3. What's wrong with a question begging argument?
4. What is the fallacy of begging the question against? How does it differ from begging the
question?
5. Against whom is the question begged in any argument that begs the question against?
6. Could the conclusion of a question-begging argument be true? Explain.
7. What is meant by burden of proof? How do commonsense beliefs matter to it?
8. Where is the burden of proof at each stage of a deliberation?
II. Each of the following arguments begs the question. Explain why.
1. Dylan is a brother. Therefore, Dylan has a sibling.
SAMPLE ANSWER: The logical thinker who rejects the conclusion would reject that Dylan is a brother.
2. Capital punishment is cruel, for it is cruel and unusual punishment. And it's demeaning to the society
that inflicts it.
*3. The mind is different from the body. Hence, the mind and the body are not the same.
4. Mount Aconcagua and Mount Whitney are both tall mountains. But Mount Aconcagua is taller than
Mount Whitney. Consequently, Mount Whitney is shorter than Mount Aconcagua.
*5. Demons are supernatural beings. Supernatural beings are only fictional. Therefore, demons do not exist.
6. Dorothy is a historian. For, she is a historian and art collector.
*7. Since Aaron is a hunter, he is someone who hunts.
8. The U.S. president and the British prime minister both oppose the treaty. Hence, it's false that both
leaders do not oppose the treaty.
*9. If a plane figure is a circle, then it is not a rectangle. Therefore, if the figure is a rectangle, then it is not
a circle.
10. The first witness is not trustworthy, since he is not reliable.
Ill. [Note: This exercise is somewhat more challenging.] For each of the above
arguments, determine whether the circularity is formal, conceptual, or both.
IV. For each of the following arguments, determine whether it would, under normal
circumstances, beg the question, beg the question against, or do both.
1. Whoever is less productive should have lower wages. Women are less productive than men. Hence,
women should have lower wages.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Begs the question against
2. Euthanasia is murder and is wrong. So, euthanasia is wrong.
*3. Fido is a puppy. Therefore, Fido is a young dog.
4. A woman has an absolute right to control her own body. And if a woman has an absolute right to
control her own body, then abortion is morally permissible. Therefore, abortion is morally permissible.
*5. Since the Democrats won the '08 presidential election, it is simply false that they didn't win.
6. Derek Jeter has an insurance policy on his cars, for it is not the case that his cars lack such a policy.
*7. The fetus is an unborn baby. Therefore, it is not the case that the fetus is not an unborn baby.
8. Anyone who is an idealist is also a loser. Thus idealists are losers.
9. Vladimir is a bachelor. Therefore, Vladimir is unmarried.
f--
(/)
z
<(
CJ
0
a:
CJ (/)
zz
:::> 0
CJ 1-
z 0…
-�
9 :::>
0 (/)
> (/)
<( <(
11&1
*10. Infanticide is always morally wrong. So, infanticide is never morally right.
11. If there is intelligent life elsewhere in the universe, then life on Earth is not unique. But life on Earth is
unique. Hence, there is no intelligent life elsewhere in the universe.
12. The right to life is God's will. Therefore, the right to life is the will of Divine Providence.
*13. Given atheism, God doesn't exist. But it is not the case that He doesn't exist, so atheism is mistaken.
14. Priscilla got a B on her philosophy paper this semester. Therefore, she turned in a philosophy paper
this semester.
15. There is life after death. Therefore, there is an afterlife.
*16. Since no person should be denied freedom, and Bruno is a person, it follows that Bruno is entitled to
freedom.
17. Magdalene is a sister. Therefore, she is a female.
18. Since capital punishment is murder, capital punishment is wrongful killing.
*19. Northfield is not far from Minneapolis. Thus Northfield is close to Minneapolis.
20. Socialism is an unjust system of government. Unjust systems of government must be abolished.
Therefore, socialism must be abolished.
V. Determine whether the following arguments are possible or impossible.
1. An argument that is cogent for a logical thinker but not rationally compelling.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Impossible
2. A valid argument that is non-cogent.
3. A sound argument that is non-cogent.
*4. A question-begging argument that is not circular.
5. A circular argument that is not fallacious.
*6. A cogent argument that begs the question against.
7. A sound argument that is cogent.
*8. A question-begging argument that is sound.
9. A question-begging argument that is rationally compelling.
*1 0. The burden of proof being on the side that has offered the most cogent argument.
VI. In the deliberation described below, determine where the burden of proof lies at
each stage: if on Carolyn, write 'C'; if on Karl, write 'K'; and if there is a dialectical
impasse, write 'I.'
1. C rejects a commonsense belief held by K.
SAMPLE ANSWER: C
2. C defends her rejection with an argument that begs the question against K.
3. C recasts her argument in a way that makes it clearly unsound.
*4. C offers a new argument that turns out be invalid.
5. C's argument undergoes another recast that makes it cogent.
*6. K advances a valid yet question-begging argument against C.
7. K offers a non-question-begging argument with clearly false premises.
*8. K recasts his argument so that it is now as cogent as C's.
VII. In the following deliberation, either Sor O has the burden of proof. Identify which
has it at any given stage in the deliberation, and mark dialectical impasses.
Explain your choice.
1. S makes a claim that challenges a commonly held belief.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Burden of proof on S. When commonsense beliefs are at issue, the burden of proof is
on the challenger.
2. S attempts to support her claim by offering an inductively weak argument.
*3. S recasts her argument so that it is now clearly valid but unsound.
4. S recasts her argument again so that it is now sound but question-begging.
*5. S's argument undergoes another recast that makes it deductively cogent.
6. 0 responds with a valid argument that begs the question against S.
*7. 0 recasts her argument so that it is now non-question-begging but plainly unsound.
8. 0 recasts her argument once more so that it is now as cogent as S's argument.
VIII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
*1. Consider the following argument: "Marriage can be only between two persons of different sexes.
Therefore, gay couples cannot be married." What's the matter with this argument?
2. Provide an argument that both begs the question and begs the question against.
3. Provide an argument that begs the question without begging the question against.
4. Provide an argument that begs the question against without begging the question.
*5. Discuss the conditions an argument must meet to be deductively cogent.
*6. An argument that is invalid always falls short of being rationally compelling, but could such an
argument be cogent? Must its conclusion be rejected? Explain your answers.
7. Imagine a debate in which two rival claims are equally well supported by observational data. Of the
two, one agrees with common sense, the other doesn't. Does this make a difference? Where is the
burden of proof? Explain.
8. Discuss what's wrong with an argument that begs the question.
9. Discuss what's wrong with an argument that begs the question against.
I
(/)
z
<(
0
<( <(
-
*10. Suppose you are engaged in a rational debate. Your opponent has just offered a seemingly adequate
argument for a claim that you wish to reject. Where is the burden of proof? What does 'burden of
proof' mean?
8.4 Complex Question
Another fallacy of presumption is complex question, which is a pattern of mistake in asking a
question that can be answered only by yes or no, but which assumes either
1. that there is only one question when there are in fact two or more, each with its own
answer, or
2. that some claim is true when in fact it is either false or, at the very least, doubtful.
Whenever this fallacy is committed, the question being asked is unfair because it
has an unjustified assumption embedded within it, in one or the other of these two ways.
An example of 1 would be a question one can imagine being asked of a presidential
candidate:
20 If elected, would you continue the best traditions of your party and promote wasteful
spending on welfare programs that only encourage laziness? Yes or no?
Clearly, this is not one question but two. The candidate may indeed want to continue the best
traditions of his party but also have no intention of promoting "wasteful spending on welfare
programs that only encourage laziness." But the interlocutor is demanding a yes or no on the
whole query at once and not allowing him to divide the question.
An example of 2 would be a question that is implicitly critical of the person being queried.
A classic case of this is that of a man who's asked,
21 Have you stopped beating your wife?
Here a 'yes' is just as bad as a 'no,' because it seems to follow from this question that the
addressee was engaged in wife beating. Questions of this sort are unfair, since the person
queried will convict himself with either answer. (Note, however, that context does matter. If a
man is actually known to be a wife beater, then posing (21) to him would not commit a fallacy.)
Consider another example: 'Tyler is a high school student who plays in a punk-rock band. He
has multiple piercings and tattoos but has never used drugs of any kind. One evening he has a
date with Dahlia to go to the movies. But when he arrives to pick her up, he meets her father,
who regards him with suspicion and says,
22 Before you take my daughter to the movies, I must ask you this: do you intend to
conceal from me your history of marijuana use?
Now, what is the correct answer to this? Obviously, 'Tyler doesn't want to answer 'yes.' But if
he answers 'no,' then that is equally to admit to marijuana use (something he's innocent of).
Either answer will convict him. Notice, however, that that is only because the question itself
is unfair. It assumes-without any supporting evidence-that the young man has used
marijuana!
It's not difficult to see the mistake here. But how is this an argument? First, the question
asks whether or not Tyler intends to conceal his history of marijuana use. If he does, then he
has a history of marijuana use. And if he doesn't, then he also has a history of marijuana use.
Assuming that he either does or doesn't, it follows that he has a history of marijuana use.
But there is a problem with these premises, since they rest on an assumption that is false
namely, that the person queried ('Tyler) does have a history of marijuana use.
Yet not all arguments that commit the complex-question fallacy are intended specifically to
trap an individual. Some consist simply in questions phrased so that any answer a respondent
gives to them must necessarily endorse an unsupported assumption built into the question
itself. Suppose that a politician, in a speech, asks,
23 Does my opponent agree with the president's disastrous economic policy which is
now leading our nation to ruin?
Because the question assumes (without anything in the context making it plausible) that the
president's economic policy is 'disastrous,' and that it is 'leading our nation to ruin,' anyone
who responds to (23), either in the affirmative or in the negative, will be implicitly endorsing
those views! Again, a fallacy of complex question has been committed, in this case by the
politician. To a complex question, it seems, any answer is a wrong answer. But that is only
because there is something wrong with the question itself. It is phrased so that it assumes
something not yet supported.
BOX 8 ■ HOW TO AVOID COMPLEX QUESTION
Beware of any yes/no question presupposing that, if the answer is yes, a questionable proposition
P (for which no argument has been offered) follows, and if you answer is no, P also follows.
8.5 False Alternatives
False alternatives is a defect in reasoning that might affect an argument containing a
disjunction as premise. A disjunction is a compound proposition with two members or
'disjuncts.' An exclusive disjunction has the form
24 Either P or Q.(but not both).
Here P and Q represent propositions standing as exclusive alternatives, because if one is true,
the other is false and vice versa. For example,
25 Either the groundhog hibernates during the winter or it continues in a state of
animation.
This is an exclusive disjunction, since it presupposes that exactly one of the alternatives is true.
By contrast, consider the inclusive disjunction
26 Apples that are either too small or too ripe are discarded.
(j)
w
>
I
<(
z
a:
w
<(
w
(j)
.....J
it
LO
co
0
w
0
z
::)
0 a:
0 (/)
zz
::) 0
0 i=
z D...
-�
g ::)
0 (/) > (/)
(f)
<{ <{
El
XI. The following arguments are instances of begging the question, begging the
question against, complex question, false alternatives, or accident. Determine
which is which. (Note that in some cases an argument could both beg
the question and beg the question against.)
1. Jane has to come to work. She may be sick, as she says, but she is needed in the office. Whenever
an employee is needed in the office, she must show up.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Accident
2. Women should not be deployed for military service, because no woman should serve in the military.
3. We've had record hot weather for two weeks. In a heat wave as bad as this, there are only two
options: either one spends all day complaining about it, or one shuts up and goes about one's work.
So we'll have to go on with our work, since complaining is not an option for us.
*4. Is MacKenzie still forcing his employees to use obsolete technology in his office?
5. Everyone should get some strenuous physical exercise every day, like running a mile before breakfast.
So, my Uncle Olaf, who is ninety-seven years old, ought to run a mile every day before breakfast.
*6. To be wealthy, you have to be either a Wall Street financier or a drug dealer. You are wealthy, but you
are not a Wall Street financier. It follows that you are a drug dealer.
7. Have they given up yet on casting a short blond actor, Daniel Craig, as James Bond?
8. Sarah had better marry Dombrowsky. For either she marries him or ends up single.
*9. In general, any average person's statistical chance of suffering a gunshot wound is minimal. So I'm not
worried about my friend Al, who just joined the police force.
10. Did Melissa manage to get along with Justin?
11. Was he able to stay out of trouble during his last visit?
*12. Murderers don't have a right to life. Since Joe is a murderer, he doesn't have a right to life.
13. Certainly there is life after death, since there are people who have lived previous lives and have
memories of those earlier selves long ago.
14. The law clearly states that if citizens fail to pay their taxes, they'll be prosecuted. So my four-year-old
cousin Egbert should be prosecuted! After all, I happen to know that he paid no taxes last year.
*15. Do you support Senator Krank's ridiculous school appropriations bill, which would bankrupt our state
government?
16. Martial arts are either taekwondo or jujitsu. Yoshizuki is trained in the martial arts, but he doesn't
practice taekwondo. Therefore, he practices jujitsu.
*17. It will surely be in the interest of the United States to abolish tariffs on commerce with nations south
of the Rio Grande, for free trade with Latin America can only be in the interest of the United States.
18. Do you really want to pass up your chance of a lifetime to invest in Swampwood Estates, Florida's
most exclusive and luxurious new residential neighborhood?
19. Were you sober last weekend?
*20. I can say whatever I want about my neighbor, O'Connor. Whether it's true or not, I can say it, and no
one can stop me! After all, the First Amendment guarantees freedom of speech in the United States.
21. If there is no substantial economic growth in our country this year, then either there will be disruptive
social upheaval or the military will overthrow the government. We're at a point now where there could
only be minimal economic growth. Therefore, we can expect a military overthrow of the government
to happen soon.
*22. Lakeesha's donation of her prize money to AIDS research was selfless. It follows that her action was
not selfish.
23. Either the United States invades Mexico or drugs cartels continue to destabilize Mexican society. Since
the United States won't intervene, it follows that drugs cartels continue to destabilize Mexican society.
24. Since media literacy is a proven tool against crime, it could be used to reform convicted murderers.
*25. Abigail has been reporting intractable insomnia since 1999. A warm glass of milk before going to bed
should end the problem for her. After all, it helps others to sleep well.
XII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
*1. 'If a principle has proved to be generally true or reliable, it's probably true all of the time.' Should we
agree with this rule? Explain your answer.
2. Suppose I find in an argument some premise that itself can be accepted only if the conclusion has
already been accepted. What's wrong with the argument? Explain the fallacy it commits.
3. Provide two circular arguments, one that begs the question and one that doesn't. What's wrong with
those arguments?
*4. Ask a complex question and explain why it is a fallacy.
■ Writing Project
The principle that we should be tolerant of the beliefs and actions of others is highly regarded
in our culture. Find at least three examples of current beliefs or actions that you think fall
beyond the reach of that principle and write a short essay entitled "Beyond Tolerance." In each
case, first construct an argument where that principle is used to contend that some episode
(of hate speech, Holocaust denial, terrorism, etc.) should be tolerated. Then explain why the
argument fails by showing that it commits the fallacy of accident.
■ Chapter Summary
Fallacies of Presumption: They make an argument fail in virtue of some unwarranted
assumption built into its premises. The argument seems OK only when the assumption is made.
They include:
1. Begging the Question. The argument features at least one premise that itself depends on
the conclusion's being true, so that it can be accepted only if one has already accepted the
conclusion.
2. Begging the Question Against. The argument features at least one controversial premise
that is assumed to be true but not argued for. Note: when a claim is controversial, an
argument that commits this fallacy is no help in discharging the burden of proof.
>
a:
<(
�
�
:::,
(J)
a:
w
l
o..
<(
I
0
0
UJ
0
z
:::,
0
a:
CJ (j)
zz
:::, 0
CJ f
z 0..
-�
�:::,
0 (j)
> (j)
< <
-
3. Complex Question. The question either has an unsupported assumption built into it or is
a conflation of two or more different questions.
4. False Alternatives. The argument features a premise with a disjunction, mistakenly taking
it to be either exclusive, when in fact both disjuncts could be true, or exhaustive, when in
fact there is a third alternative.
5. Accident. The argument assumes that some principle generally applicable is applicable
also in the anomalous case, when in fact it isn't.
■ Key Words
Presumption
Begging the question
Begging the question against
Burden of proof
Commonsense belief
Vicious circularity
Formal circularity
Conceptual circularity
Complex question
False alternatives
Accident
Benign circularity
CHAPTER
From Unclear
Language to Unclear
Reasoning
This chapter considers some common forms of unclarity in language, and the ways
in which they lead to unclarity in reasoning. Its topics will include
Three types of linguistic unclarity that may lead to fallacies: vagueness, ambiguity, and
confused predication.
■ The heap paradox.
■ The fallacy of slippery slope.
The fallacy of equivocation.
■ The fallacy of amphiboly.
■ The fallacy of composition.
The fallacy of division.
187
w
00 �z
0z
zo <( (fJ
_J <(
a: w
<( a:
w a:
_J <( Ow z _J
:::> 0
LZ
0 :::> a: 0 u.. f-
laP.P.I
….
9.1 Unclear Language and Argument Failure
Vagueness, ambiguity, and confused predication are three different sources of unclear
language. Each may lead to argument failure, and we shall find, rooted in these defects, several
types of informal fallacy as well as a type of puzzling argument. When an expression is vague
to a significant degree, it is unclear whether it applies to certain things. For instance, it’s
unclear whether ‘rich’ applies to Betty, who has $900,000 in her bank account. She’s certainly
doing well, but she’s not even a millionaire, much less a billionaire! The problem is that ‘rich’ is
a vague word: for some cases, it’s not clear what (or who) counts as being ‘rich.’ By contrast,
when an expression is ambiguous to a significant degree, it has more than one meaning and
reference, and it is unclear which one is intended by its user. For example, it is unclear whether
“challenging arguments” means either the act of disputing some arguments or complex
arguments that are difficult to follow. Roughly, the reference of an expression is what the
expression applies to, while its meaning is its content. Consider
1 The sum of 1+1
2 The smallest even number.
Both (1) and (2) may be used to refer to the same thing, since they both apply to the same
number-namely, the number 2. Yet (1) and (2) don’t have the same content, which is equivalent
to saying that they don’t have the same meaning, for
MEANING = CONTENT
Since reference and meaning belong to the semantic dimension of a language, vagueness and
ambiguity are two different forms of semantic unclarity. Each may undermine an argument by
affecting some of the terms or concepts that make up its premises and conclusion.
Confused predication, on the other hand, also amounts to semantic unclarity, but it can
arise only at the level of relations between statements in an argument. That is, confused predi
cation is a fallacy involving a certain error committed in using some predicate, or expression
that attributes some feature or quality to a thing- for example, ‘occupying 60 percent of the
surface of the Earth’ in the conclusion of this argument:
3 Since oceans occupy 60 percent of the surface of the Earth and the Mediterranean is
an ocean, therefore the Mediterranean occupies 60 percent of the surface of the
Earth.
While ‘occupying 60 percent of the surface of the Earth’ might be truly predicated of all oceans
taken collectively, it obviously fails to be true of the Mediterranean Sea. The confusion in (3) is
a common type of mistake that stems from an erroneous inference involving a predicate (we’ll
have more to say about predicates later in this chapter).
Linguistic unclarity rooted in any of these phenomena (confused predication, vagueness,
or ambiguity) can render an argument fallacious. Yet before we examine common ways
in which this may happen, we must ask why such mistakes matter to logical thinking at all.
BOX 1 ■ SOME FALLACIES OF UNCLEAR LANGUAGE AND
A PARADOX
I
Heap
I paradox
Vagueness
Slippery
Slope
Equivocation
UNCLEAR
Ambiguity
LANGUAGE
Amphiboly
Composition
Confused
Predication
Division
Two millennia ago, Greek philosophers pointed out that unclarity in language is a sign of
unclarity in reasoning. Today we’d say much the same. Assuming that speakers are sincere,
what they say is what they believe. And since beliefs are the building blocks of their reasoning,
it is then quite likely that any unclarity in what they say results from unclarity in how they rea
son (for more on this topic, see Chapters 2. and 3).
9.2 Semantic Unclarity
Vagueness and ambiguity are forms of semantic unclarity that may affect linguistic expressions
of different kinds, as well as the logical relations between them. When an expression is vague, it
is unclear whether or not certain cases fall within its reference. When an expression is ambiguous,
it is unclear which of its possible meanings is the one intended by the speaker. Suppose some
one says
4 She got the cup.
Furthermore, this is said in a room where there are several women, without pointing to any
one in particular. In this context, it is unclear to whom the word ‘she’ applies. At the same time,
the term ‘cup’ is ambiguous, since it may equally mean and refer to either ‘bowl-shaped drink
ing vessel’ or ‘sports trophy.’ Furthermore, if we assume that it is used to refer to a drinking
vessel, it is unclear just how wide the range of its application may be. Does it apply, for exam
ple, to coffee mugs? What about beer tankards? These seem borderline cases about which ‘cup’
neither definitely applies nor definitely fails to apply. Hence, ‘cup’ is not only ambiguous, but
also to some degree vague.
a:
_J
u
z
::J
u
f-
z
0
zZ
0 ::>
a: 0
u.. I-
BOX 2 ■ VAGUENESS AND AMBIGUITY
■ When an expression is vague, there are borderline cases where it is unclear whether the
expression applies.
■ When an expression is ambiguous, it has more than one meaning and sometimes more than
one reference.
Vagueness and ambiguity are, however, also found at a higher level in the statements that
make up arguments. Here the worst-case scenario is one where a defect of either type renders
an argument misleading. In any such argument, although its conclusion might at first appear
acceptable on the basis of the argument’s premises, a closer look could show that in fact it’s
not. The premises actually provide no support for it.
Logical thinkers should be alert for misleading arguments and try, through careful, case
by-case scrutiny, to unmask fallacies lurking behind vague or ambiguous language.
These two forms of semantic unclarity are unavoidable features of many everyday
arguments. Such arguments are, after all, cast in a natural language, which, unlike a formal
language, is rich in semantic connotations. For example, suppose that a college instructor, on
the day of an examination, receives this phone message on her answering machine:
5 This is Mary. I was at the bank during the test, so I’d like to take the makeup.
Unable to recognize the voice, and aware of several financial institutions as well as a river
nearby, the instructor cannot make much of (5). For one thing, of the several students
named ‘Mary’ who missed the exam, it is unclear who the caller in (s) is. Furthermore, of the
two meanings of ‘bank’ possible in (5), either ‘financial institution’ or ‘side of a river,’ it is
unclear which one is intended. Suppose the student who left the message later sends a note
from the local Citibank branch attesting that, on the date of the exam, she, Mary McDonald,
had to go there to refinance her mortgage. Putting two and two together, the instructor
reasons that
6 Mary McDonald was the student who reported her absence. She can prove she was at
the local Citibank branch the day of the exam. Thus she qualifies for the makeup.
No ambiguity remains now: a look at contextual information has eliminated the semantic
unclarity in (s) above.
Yet sometimes semantic unclarity bearing on the soundness or strength of an argument
persists even after we have engaged in a charitable and faithful reconstruction of the argu
ment. In that case, we must reject the argument on the ground that its premises provide no
support for its conclusion, even though they might at first appear to support it. As we shall
presently see in detail, each of these two types of semantic unclarity can render an argument
misleading.
BOX 3 ■ HOW TO AVOID AMBIGUITY AND VAGUENESS
Ambiguity and vagueness are a matter of degree. Although they affect most expressions in
natural languages (which is in part why symbolic logic has developed formal languages to study
logical relations such as inference), the fog they raise can often be thinned by looking at the context
that is, other linguistic expressions surrounding the affected ones, and factors in the arguer’s
environment. When we are engaged in argument reconstruction, the principles of charity and
faithfulness recommend that we check the context, when available, to gain semantic clarity.
9.3 Vagueness
Vagueness is at the root of some philosophically interesting puzzling arguments and also of
many fallacious ones. Later in this section, we’ll examine some cases of each. But first, let’s
consider a shortcoming common to all arguments affected by vagueness: indeterminacy.
When either the premise or conclusion of an argument is significantly vague, that
statement is indeterminate: neither determinately true nor determinately false. Such
indeterminacy undermines the argument as a whole.
This is because, as you may recall, to be deductively sound or inductively strong, an argu
ment must have premises that are determinately true. Without that, it counts as neither.
Consider this argument:
7 1. Tall buildings in Chicago are in danger of terrorist attacks.
2. The 30-story Nussbaum Building in Chicago is a tall building.
3. The 30-story Nussbaum Building in Chicago is in danger of terrorist attacks.
This argument seems valid, since if its premises are true, its conclusion cannot be false. At the
same time, it also seems unsound, for soundness requires determinately true premises, and
premise 2 suffers from a significant degree of vagueness: putting aside the problem that tall
ness is relative, although a 100-story building is clearly tall (even by Chicago standards) and a
2-story building clearly not tall, it is unclear whether a 30-story building is tall in Chicago. No
contextual information is available to reduce the vagueness of premise 2, which results from
the two facts described in Box 4. The problem is that there is no determinate point or cutoff
between tall Chicago buildings and Chicago buildings that are not tall.
BOX 4 ■ WHAT’S WRONG WITH ARGUMENT 7?
1. It uses the expression ‘tall,’ which has no clear cutoff point between the cases to which it
determinately applies and those to which it determinately does not apply.
2. The 30-story Nussbaum Building is among the borderline cases of things about which it is
indeterminate whether that word applies or not. It is neither determinately tall nor
determinately not tall.
(/)
(/)
w
z
w
::J
0
<(
>
(‘)
0)
w
(.’) (.’) <( z :J -
CJ z
zo
<( (j)
_J <(
a: w
<( a:
w a:
_J <(
Ow z _J
:J 0
�z
0 :J
a: 0
LL f-
When a statement has a vague term applied to a borderline case, that statement is neither
determinately true nor determinately false. Try this yourself: run another series with, for
example, 'cold,' beginning with the determinately true statement, 'A temperature of zero degrees
Fahrenheit is cold,' and continuing to a point where you 'cannot draw the line.' Is it 47 degrees?
48 degrees? 50? Again, any cutoff point in the series would be rather arbitrary.
Keep in mind, however, that vague terms may have non-vague occurrences. Compare
8 The 30-story Nussbaum Building is tall.
9 The 100-story John Hancock Building is tall.
10 The one-story Exxon Station on Route 10 is tall.
While (8) is indeterminate, (9) seems determinately true and (10) determinately false.
BOX 5 ■ SUMMARY OF VAGUENESS
When a term is vague,
■ It is indeterminate whether it applies or not to certain borderline cases.
■ There is no cutoff between the cases to which it determinately applies and those to
which it determinately does not.
When a statement is vague, it is neither determinately true nor determinately false.
The Heap Paradox
Every bit as puzzling to us today as it was to the philosophers of ancient Greece who discov
ered it is the heap paradox, also called 'argument from the heap' or 'sorites' (from the Greek,
soros, 'a heap'). The argument begins with obviously true premises, but, because they contain a
vague term, ends with an obviously false conclusion:
11 1. One grain of sand is not a heap.
2. If 1 grain of sand is not a heap, then 2 grains of sand are not a heap.
3. If 2 grains of sand are not a heap, then 3 grains of sand are not a heap.
4. If 3 grains of sand are not a heap, then 4 grains of sand are not a heap.
5. If 4 grains of sand are not a heap, then ...
6. A large number (say, a million) grains of sand are not a heap.
Given (u), no matter how many grains of sand there are, they never make up a heap.
Something has gone wrong in (u), but since it is difficult to tell what, (11) is a puzzle or para
dox. After all, it seems that,
A. The argument is valid.
B. Its premises are true.
C. Its conclusion is false.
D. But a valid argument can't have true premises and a false conclusion.
Like other heap arguments, (11) then creates a paradox, for D is true by definition of 'valid
argument.' Therefore, A, B, and C cannot all be true, but it is difficult to say which of them
is false.
A paradox is a puzzle without apparent solution involving claims that cannot
all be true at once, even though each seems independently true. Standardly,
a paradox may be dealt with in one or the other of two ways: it may be solved
or it may be dissolved. To solve a paradox, at least one of its claims must be
shown false. To dissolve it, it has to be shown that the claims are not really
inconsistent.
Until we do either the one or the other, the paradox remains. Since antiquity, the heap
paradox has resisted many attempts of both kinds, all of which have turned out to be flawed in
one way or another.
Let's now use another vague word, 'child,' to run a simplified heap paradox.
12 1. A 3-year-old is a child.
2. If a 3-year-old is a child, then a 4-year-old is a child.
3. If a 4-year-old is a child, then ...
4. A 90-year-old is a child.
Again, the argument seems valid, its premises true, and its conclusion false. Premise 2 suggest
a chain of premises such as
13 If a 4-year-old is a child, then a 5-year-old is a child.
14 If a 5-year-old is a child, then a 6-year-old is a child.
The series eventually reaches borderline cases such as a 14-year-old or a 15-year-old, about
whom to the term 'child' neither clearly applies nor doesn't apply. There is no cutoff point
between these and the previous cases, to which the word clearly applies. Or between these and
the following case, to which the word clearly doesn't apply:
15 A no-year-old person is a child.
The unclarity affecting (12), then, is owing to the vagueness of the word 'child.'
More needs to be said about what goes wrong in the heap argument, but on the basis of
its puzzling aspects, it has all the marks of a paradox.
The above arguments run into the heap paradox because they feature words such as
'heap' and 'child,' which are affected by vagueness.
(/)
(/)
w
z
w
:J
0
<(
C?
Ol
ml
w
C) C)
<{ z ::J -
C) z
zo
<{ (/)
....J <{
a: w
<{ a:
w a:
....J <{
Ow
z ....J
::J 0
�z
0 ::J
a: 0
lJ.. I-
IDI
The Slippery-Slope Fallacy
By contrast with the heap paradox, we can tell what has gone wrong in arguments that commit
the fallacy of concern here:
A slippery-slope argument proceeds from a premise about a harmless scenario to
one or more premises about apparently similar scenarios that are taken to have
unwelcome consequences, either flouting well-accepted rules or leading to disaster.
The argument would commit a fallacy just in case there is no good reason to think
■ That the scenarios in question are analogous in the way assumed in the
argument, or
■ That the chain of events envisioned will in fact happen as assumed in the argument.
Thus arguments that commit this fallacy begin with a premise that seems clearly true and
move through a continuum of cases to a conclusion that appears to be the unavoidable result
of sound reasoning. Yet close scrutiny often shows that it isn't sound. Imagine two arguments
on opposite sides of a City Council debate on whether to enact legislation requiring
registration of handguns.
16 Council Member Robinson argues, "If we pass a law requiring registration of
handguns, that will lead inevitably to other laws requiring registration of all firearms,
including hunting weapons. And that will then mean that the government will have a
list of all the gun owners. But if the government has such a list, the next inevitable
step is the confiscation of all weapons by the government. From this, it is but a small
step to dictatorship and the end of freedom."
16' Council Member Richardson replies, "If we fail to pass a law requiring the registra
tion of handguns, these guns will become easier and easier to obtain. And this will
mean that criminals and psychopaths of every description will have their pick of
dangerous firearms, including assault weapons. If that happens, crime will increase
exponentially and our cities will become lawless battlefields. Ultimately, all social
order will break down. Armed thugs will run roughshod over the rights of citizens as
our nation descends into anarchy."
The thing to notice in this debate is that both of these arguments commit the slippery-slope
fallacy. They both begin by issuing a warning about an apparently innocent first step and then
predict a succession of worsening conditions, leading ultimately to disaster, if the initial step is
taken (Robinson) or not taken (Richardson). But is there really any good reason to think that
the hopeless slide to catastrophe envisioned in either of these two very different arguments
really would happen? Of course, such things could happen. But we're not justified in believing
it would on the basis of the "reasons" presented here. Both of these council members are
offering arguments that are little more that speculative fearmongering and hype. They plainly
commit slippery slope.
In a different variant of the slippery-slope argument, an argument may fail because there
is no good reason to think that an assumed similarity between premises actually obtains.
Suppose you arrive five minutes late to a wedding without making much of it. The conven
tional rule is that arriving, say, sixty minutes late to a wedding is a serious breach of etiquette
and therefore not acceptable. Someone thinks that your five-minute delay is not acceptable,
because allowing it is not significantly different from allowing a sixty-minute delay, which
would in effect overthrow that rule altogether. This example of slippery-slope fallacy runs,
17 Whatever justifies arriving five minutes late to a wedding would justify arriving
six minutes late, seven minutes late, ... and even sixty minutes late! Thus accepting a
justification for arriving five minutes late would amount to overthrowing an
important social convention.
Clearly there is a kind of reasoning by analogy here, since consistency requires that we treat like
cases alike, ascribing the same qualities to each pair of relevantly similar cases in the series
(six minutes late is not much different from seven minutes late, which is itself not much different
from eight minutes late, etc.). But the background assumption seems to be that a sequence of
small differences can never amount to a substantial difference between any two points in the
sequence. And that's plainly false. Small differences can sometimes add up to a big difference in
the end. Furthermore, even in the comparison of two similar cases, it may turn out that some
predicates are true of one without being true of the other. For example, on some highways the
law stipulates a speed limit of 70 miles per hour. Now, there is no significant difference in speed
between 70 miles per hour and 71 miles per hour; but because of the law, driving at 70 miles per
hour on those highways is legal, while driving at 71 is technically illegal. So the predicate 'legal'
truly applies in one case but not in the other, even though they are otherwise not substantially
different. We may conclude that any argument committing the slippery-slope fallacy rests on this
false principle: What is true of A is also true of Z, provided there is a series of cases B, C, ... , Y
between A and Z that differ from each other only minimally.
BOX 6 ■ HOW TO AVOID THE SLIPPERY-SLOPE FALLACY
Reject the principle fueling a slippery-slope argument, for that something is true of some given
case doesn't guarantee that it's likewise true of any other similar case. Although it is reasonable
that similar cases share many predicates, small differences in a series of cases can add up to a big
difference between the initial case and the one featured in the slippery-slope argument's
conclusion. The slippery-slope arguer fails to take this into account.
9.4 Ambiguity
Vagueness must be distinguished from ambiguity. As we have seen, a word or phrase is vague
if its reference is indeterminate, so that it is unclear whether or not it applies to a certain case.
But ambiguity is a different kind of semantic unclarity that is also apt to cause havoc in argu
ments, and therefore is equally likely to mislead. A word is ambiguous if it has more than one
meaning and a given context makes unclear which meaning is intended.
>
I-
::)
C)
CD
::’?
<(
w
0
0
I-
::J
CJ
ai
�
<{
ma
w
('J ('J
a:
w
_J
w
a:
a:
0 U)
��
g�
ow
> a:
<( 0..
MU•
10.1 Fallacies of Relevance
Another source of error in reasoning that can cause an argument to be misleading is the
failure of premises to be relevant to the conclusion they are offered to support. Even if a
premise is plainly true, if it is also irrelevant to the conclusion it is supposedly backing up, then
it cannot count as a reason for it, and the argument fails. Arguments that are fallacious by
virtue of having irrelevant premises often rely on distractions that draw attention away from
what truly matters for the conclusions at hand, and thus are sometimes employed as rhetorical
tricks by artful persuaders who aim to influence us by psychologically effective but logically
defective means. There are several types of informal fallacy that manifest this form of error,
often known as 'fallacies of relevance.' We'll consider six of them here.
BOX 1 ■ FALLACIES OF RELEVANCE
I FALLACIES OF
I
. RELEVANCE .
APPEAL TO APPEAL TO
PITY FORCE
.----� _-_--._-_-_-_-_,-'
AD HOMINEM
BESIDE THE jsTRA� MANI POINT .
10.2 Appeal to Pity
One type of fallacy of relevance is the appeal to pity (also called ad misericordiam).
An argument commits the fallacy of appeal to pity if and only if its premises attempt
to arouse feelings of sympathy as a means of supporting its conclusion.
Consider, for example, an argument that was once made on behalf of clemency for Rudolf
Hess, a close associate of Hitler arrested in Britain during World War II and later sentenced to
life imprisonment for war crimes. In 1982, when Hess was old and in poor health, some people
argued that he should be freed from prison. The argument went this way:
1 1. Hess has already spent more than forty years in prison.
2. He is in his eighties now and his health is failing.
3. This elderly man should be permitted to spend his last years with his family.
4. Hess should be granted clemency.
But Hess's age and failing health were irrelevant to the real issue: his guilt as one of the
founders of a regime that had terrorized Europe. Many Russians, whose country had suffered
millions of deaths at the hands of the German invaders, recognized this argument as an
appeal to pity and objected vigorously. As a result, Hess's sentence was never commuted and
he died in prison.
A similar argument was offered recently by the mother of a sea pirate, who begged the
president of the United States for leniency in her son's case on the grounds that he was "lured
into piracy by older friends." According to a report in the Associated Press, the pirate himself
expressed contrition. "I am very, very sorry about what we did," he said through an
interpreter. "All of this was about the problems in Somalia." But even if we do feel sorry for
him, in view of his wretched existence in a war-torn, lawless land, that is hardly enough to
justify the murder of innocent merchant seamen on foreign-flag ships. The argument is
plainly an appeal to pity.
It's worth noting, however, that it's not only on behalf of scoundrels and criminals that
people resort to the appeal to pity. We find it in everyday life in many guises, including some
uses we may (wrongly) think free of this fallacy-for example, when a student argues,
2 You gave me a B in this course, but . . . can't you give me an A? If I don't have an A,
then it'll mean that my grade average will fall, and I won't be able to get into law
school! And I've been working hard all semester.
The argument in fact is:
2' 1. I've been working hard in this course.
2. Any grade below an A would adversely affect my chances for law school.
3. I should get an A in this course.
This argument commits the fallacy of appeal to pity. But not because of premise 1: plainly, how
hard the student has been working is not relevant to its conclusion, but that is the fallacy
known as 'beside the point' (more on this later). What's making the argument count as an
appeal to pity is premise 2: that premise shows that the argument attempts to support its
conclusion by making the professor feel sorry for the student. It might succeed in doing that,
but it fails to make its conclusion rationally acceptable.
More generally, an appeal to pity is a fallacious argument trading on the fact that feeling
sorry for someone is often psychologically motivating. Yet that is not a good reason for the
argument's conclusion. Logical thinkers would want to be able to recognize and avoid this
fallacy. For some tips on this, see Box 2.
, BOX 2 ■ HOW TO AVOID APPEAL TO PITY
1. An argument whose premises attempt to provoke feelings of sympathy that might move an
audience to accept its conclusion commits the fallacy of appeal to pity.
2. Any such argument should be rejected, since it provides no reason relevant to its conclusion
that is, it provides no rational support for it.
10.3 Appeal to Force
Another informal fallacy trading on feelings, though in an entirely different way, is the appeal
to force (sometimes called ad baculum, literally, 'to the stick').
w
0
a:
0
LL
0
f
__J
<{
w
0..
0..
<{
(')
0
1-
z
_J w
er:
a:
” Cf)
z
w
– Cf)
��
ow
> a:
<( a..
llml
Sometimes reasoning that commits the fallacy of appeal to emotion rests on a clever use
of images that provoke a strong emotional response. When President Lyndon Johnson was
running for reelection in 1964, his campaign sought to capitalize on prevalent voter fears about
the alleged recklessness of his opponent, Senator Barry Goldwater. In a charged, Cold War era,
some feared that Goldwater might be too quick to resort to nuclear weapons, and Johnson's
campaigners wanted to exploit this uneasiness. So the Democratic Party ran a television
commercial that opened with a view a of sunny meadow and a little girl picking flowers, then
cut to a dark screen with the fiery mushroom cloud of a nuclear explosion billowing up into
the night sky. Across a black screen the message then flashed: 'VOTE FOR PRESIDENT
JOHNSON.' One of the most notorious examples of emotively charged images in the history
of political advertising, the commercial was widely denounced as tasteless, prompting
Democrats to withdraw it.
BOX 4 ■ HOW TO AVOID APPEAL TO EMOTION
1. Be on guard for arguments that attempt, through the use of emotively charged words or
images, to elicit a strong psychological response conducive to the acceptance of its
conclusion.
2. Any such argument commits the fallacy of appeal to emotion and should be rejected. Why?
Because its premises offer only "reasons" that are irrelevant, in the way suggested in (1), to the
argument's conclusion. No such argument can provide rational support for its conclusion.
The Bandwagon Appeal
Some forms of emotional appeal are intended to take advantage of common feelings that
seem to be part of human nature, such as the desire not to miss out on the latest trends-for
example, when books are marketed as 'best sellers' or a film is touted as 'the Number One Hit
Movie of the Summer!' This so-called bandwagon appeal exploits our desire to join in with the
common experiences of others and not be left out. But the reasons offered for buying the book
or seeing the movie merely note their popular appeal, not their quality. A best seller might be
only a shallow entertainment, a hit movie little more than a television sitcom. That they're
widely sought does nothing to support the claim that they're worth seeking.
Appeal to Vanity
Appeal to vanity (sometimes called 'snob appeal') is another of the varieties of ad populum
this time trying to exploit people's unspoken fears about self-esteem. When a car is advertised
as in (7), the advertiser attempts to persuade prospective buyers to buy the car by making an
appeal to their vanity.
7 Not for everyone-this is the car that tells the world who you are!
In another example of this argumentation tactic, Virgin Atlantic Airways has decided to attract
customers to its premium-class service by calling it, not 'first class,' but 'Upper Class.' Can you
see what is going on here?
10.5 Ad Hominem
Another way arguments can fail because of irrelevant premises is the very common fallacy of
ad hominem (literally, 'to the man'), which has less to do with emotion than with personal
attack. It is sometimes called 'argument against the person,' but we'll call it by its Latin name,
since that has now come to be familiar in everyday usage.
An argument commits the fallacy of ad hominem if and only if it attempts to discredit
someone's-or some group's-argument, point of view, or achievement by means of
personal attack.
That is, the fallacious ad hominem rests on some personal consideration strictly irrelevant
to the matter at hand, which is intended to undermine someone's credibility, as a means of
indirectly attacking the person's position or argument. The problem with such an ad hominem,
of course, is that in this way the question of the real merit of that person's position is evaded.
Instead, the ad hominem offers only a cheap shot aimed at the person herself. Before turning to
some specific arguments of this sort, notice that they all fail to support their conclusions-yet
they can be recognized easily and avoided in the way suggested in Box 5.
Examples of ad hominem are, unfortunately, easy to find-sometimes committed by
people you'd not expect to be committing fallacies. Planned Parenthood recently ran a series of
advertisements on buses and subways that featured a photo of several grumpy-looking men in
suits. Across the photo was mounted the ad copy, which read, "79% of abortion opponents are
men. 100% of them will never be pregnant." We may smile at this rhetorically clever
juxtaposition of image and slogan, but, make no mistake, this is an ad hominem against male
opponents of abortion. Instead of focusing on what those men's objections to abortion may be,
the effect of the ad is simply to dismiss the objections as men's views. But the views of men
on abortion or any other topic-cannot be legitimately rejected solely on the basis of their
provenance (that they are "men's views"). Rather, the question is: Are these views well
supported? It's not whose views they are that matters, but do the proponents have good or bad
arguments for their claims?
Suppose a new political scandal erupts in Washington. Senator Dunster has been caught
using public funds to pay for expensive luxury vacations for himself and his family, and
another legislator, Senator Brewster, has taken to the Senate floor to denounce this
impropriety. But Dunster is a Harvard man and cannot resist pointing out that Brewster's
college days were spent at Yale. In a speech, Dunster loudly responds,
8 These charges are all false! And these unfounded accusations are coming from
exactly the place we would expect. Apparently Senator Brewster, like all Yalies, cannot
resist the temptation to besmirch the reputation of a Harvard man!
Here Senator Dunster's argument is an ad hominem that attempts to discredit Brewster's
statements, not by speaking to their content (the accusations of impropriety), but by pointing
to Brewster's personal background-the fact that he is a Yale graduate. Its clear assumptions
are that all Yalies are naturally prejudiced against Harvard graduates, and that that is why
Brewster is saying these things! But Dunster's argument simply engages in personal attack:
�
w
z
�
0
I
0
<(
"'.
0
r
z
<( > w
_j
w
a:
a:
CJ (/)
��
e�
ow
> a:
<( 0..
it introduces an irrelevant consideration that has no power to actually discredit the opponent's
claim (though it may appear to do so).
The thing to keep in mind, again, is that it's not who says it that makes a claim well
supported or not, but rather whether there are in fact good reasons to back it up. Those reasons
should be judged on their own merits: either they provide some support for the claim, or they
don't. In our example, we would of course need to hear Senator Brewster 's argument
presumably citing facts in support of the conclusion that Dunster had behaved
inappropriately-in order to determine this.
BOX 5 ■ HOW TO AVOID A FALLACIOUS AD HOMINEM
1. Beware of any argument that appeals to some personal facts (or alleged facts) that are
irrelevant to its conclusion.
2. Any such argument commits the fallacy of ad hominem and should be rejected, for its
premises are irrelevant to its conclusion-that is, they are offered as a means of attempting
to discredit an argument or point of view by discrediting the person who presents it.
The Abusive Ad Hominem
Sometimes ad hominem arguments attack a person's character. Suppose a moviegoer announces,
9 I have no desire to see Woody Allen's latest movie. I'm sure it's worthless, and I wouldn't
waste my money on it-not after what I know about him now! He betrayed Mia Farrow
and broke her heart when he became romantically involved with Mia's adopted daughter,
Soon-Yi Previn. So his movies are without artistic merit, as far as I'm concerned.
Now, (9) plainly commits the fallacy of ad hominem, since it seeks to discredit Woody Allen as a
film director not by invoking evidence that his movies are artistically questionable, but by a
personal attack that refers to his relationship to Soon-Yi Previn (whom he later married). But
this ad hominem is of a more abusive sort, since it attacks Allen's character-he is denounced
on moral grounds as a 'betrayer,' which is, of course, a term of contempt. But, whatever we may
think of Allen's personal qualities, does any of that prove that his films are bad? Isn't all of that
simply irrelevant to an assessment of his art?
Tu Quoque
Finally, the fallacy of ad hominem is also committed when one tries to refute someone's point
of view by calling attention to the person's hypocrisy regarding that very point of view. This is
sometimes called 'tu quoque' (literally, 'you also'). For example, consider how Thomas
Jefferson's writings must have sounded to the British in his day. Jefferson famously wrote, in
the Declaration of Independence, "We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are
created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that
among these are Life, Liberty, and the pursuit of Happiness." But one can easily imagine how
this must have been received in conservative circles in Britain in 1776. Tories certainly
regarded this lofty language as risible political rhetoric, since they knew very well that
Jefferson was himself a prominent slave holder. In London, Dr. Samuel Johnson scoffed,
"How is it that we hear the loudest yelps for 'liberty' among the drivers of Negroes?" Johnson's
remark could be expanded into an extended argument that looks like this:
10 1. Jefferson claims that all men are created equal and have rights to liberty.
2. But Jefferson himself is a slave owner.
3. He preaches lofty principles for others that he does not practice himself.
4. Jefferson's claims about liberty and equality are false.
Yet if any did actually offer such an argument, it would have committed the fallacy of tu quoque, a
form of ad hominem. The imagined argument, after all, tries to bring a personal matter-Jefferson's
real-life hypocrisy about race and human nature-into the discussion to cast doubt on his
assertions about human equality and rights. Now, it is of course true that the Sage of Monticello
did not permit his own black slaves to enjoy the very liberty and equality he so forcefully advocated
for himself and his fellow white men. But did that personal failure go any way at all toward
showing that Jefferson's claims about liberty and equality were false? Naturally, we all think that
people should not be hypocrites. People should practice what they preach. Yet if someone fails to
heed this moral maxim, and we point out his hypocrisy, we have not thereby proved that what he
preaches is false. In fact, we are only indulging in a form of ad hominem, a tu quoque.
Nonfallacious Ad Hominem
Before we leave the discussion of ad hominem, there remains one important clarification that
should be added. Some uses of argument against the person are not fallacious, for there are
contexts in which such an argument may be in order. In public life, for instance, the moral
character of a politician may be a highly relevant issue to raise during a campaign, since we do
very reasonably expect our elected leaders to be trustworthy. In the second example given
above, Senator Brewster's speech calling Senator Dunster's personal rectitude into question
amounts to a kind of personal attack, but it commits no fallacy (as does Dunster's reply), since
conduct that is unethical (or illegal!) would not be irrelevant to an assessment of a person's
fitness to serve as a senator. Brewster's remarks, then, could justifiably be seen as an ad hominem
argument but not a fallacious one, for they commit no fallacy of irrelevant premises.
Similarly, in the Anglo-American system of justice, which employs an adversarial model in
court-with attorneys on opposing sides each presenting an argument for their client's case
and trying to undermine their opponent's position-some of what happens in the courtroom
may appear to be ad hominem. Here, after all, attorneys might try to discredit a witness by
presenting evidence about his personal life.
But in fact this does not amount to a fallacious ad hominem at all, since in the courtroom,
the reliability of a witness is not irrelevant. Given that the purpose of a witness just is to give
testimony, it is highly relevant to know whether the person can be believed or not. Thus an
attorney does not commit a fallacy of ad hominem when she appeals to relevant personal
matters in an attempt to discredit the claims made by a witness. An attorney's job is to defend
her client's interest by aggressively pressing his case, and part of that may include presenting
facts about a witness's background and personal life in an effort to undermine his credibility.
This is a kind of personal attack, but it commits no fallacy.
�
w
z
�
0
I
0
w
….)
w
0:
0:
C) (fJ
��
e�
ow
> 0:
<( Q.
WU•
Logical thinkers must bear in mind that courtroom procedure is a specialized subject in
the law, and that we're not attempting here to venture into its complexities. When one is called
to serve on a jury, one should follow the instructions of the judge. The important thing to
notice now, however, is simply that there can be some uses of ad hominem that are not
fallacious, and that it is the context that determines when this is so.
10.6 Beside the Point
An argument might commit a fallacy of relevance by offering premises that simply have little
or nothing to do with its conclusion. Maybe they support some conclusion, but they don't
support the one given by the argument. When this happens, the argument commits a beside
the-point fallacy (also known as ignoratio elenchi).
An argument commits the fallacy of beside the point if and only if its premises fail to
support its conclusion by failing to be logically related to its conclusion, though they
may support some other conclusion.
Faced with an argument of this sort, we may at first find ourselves unable to identify the
source of the confusion. For example, imagine that opponents of cruelty to animals introduce
legislation to ban the mistreatment of chickens, pigs, and cows in certain 'factory farms.' But
suppose the corporations who own the farms respond,
11 These farms are not cruel to animals. After all, the farms provide the food that most
consumers want, and they do so in a manner that is cost-effective; moreover, these
poultry, pork, and beef products are nourishing and contribute to the overall health
of American families.
The odd thing about (11) is that nothing in its premises contributes toward providing support
for the conclusion, 'These farms are not cruel to animals.' Perhaps the premises support some
conclusion. But they don't support that one, since they offer no reason to think that the factory
farms in question are not cruel. As a result, (11) commits the beside the point fallacy.
Here's another example that does so as well. Early in Barack Obama's administration, a
state dinner at the White House was attended by a local couple who had not been invited and
had no authorization to enter the White House. They were, in effect, party crashers.
Threatened with prosecution under federal law for having breached White House security,
they responded that they should not be prosecuted because they had "made a sacrifice in time
BOX 6 ■ HOW TO AVOID THE BESIDE-THE-POINT FALLACY
Logical thinkers should be on guard for
1. Arguments whose premises are simply irrelevant to proving the conclusion.
2. Any such argument is defective, even if nothing else is wrong with it; it commits a
beside-the-point fallacy and should be rejected.
and money to get ready for the party." Now, let us suppose that it's true that they had made
such a sacrifice. Even so, how is that relevant to their claim that they do not deserve
prosecution for breaking the law? The proposed "reason" why they should not be prosecuted
(namely, the alleged "sacrifice in time and money") is not a reason that supports the
conclusion. This argument is plainly an instance of the beside-the-point fallacy.
Yet another example of this type of mistake was inadvertently provided by a radio listener
who responded to a BBC program predicting a crisis of overpopulation in the United Kingdom
by 2051. "We can meet this challenge," the listener confidently asserted, "because we all stood
together as one people when we were fighting the Nazis." But there is more than one problem
in this argument, not least of them the fact that none of the Britons who fought the Germans
in World War II are likely to be alive in 2051. So, whatever the coping skills of those who
prevailed in Britain's Finest Hour, their application in the envisaged crisis to come at mid
century seems unlikely. Moreover, it is not at all clear how a nation's possessing the military
skills necessary to defeat Hitler proves anything at all about their ability to overcome an
entirely different sort of problem in the foreseen population crisis. Thus the argument is only
a beside-the-point fallacy. Its premise, though manifestly true, provides no support for the
conclusion.
12 1. We all stood together as one people when we were fighting the Nazis.
2. We can meet the coming challenge of overpopulation.
10. 7 Straw Man
Finally, let us consider a type of informal fallacy committed by any argument where the view of
an opponent is misrepresented so that it becomes vulnerable to certain objections. The distorted
view may consist of a statement or a group of related statements (i.e., a position or a theory).
Typically ignored in such distortions are charity and faithfulness, the principles of argument
reconstruction discussed in Chapter 4. Given the principle of charity, interpreting someone else's
view requires that we maximize the truth of each of its parts (in the case of an argument,
premises and conclusion) and the strength of the logical relation between them. Given the
principle of faithfulness, such interpretation requires that we strive for maximum fidelity to the
author's intentions. It is precisely the lack of charity, faithfulness, or both, in the interpretation of
the views of others with whom the arguer disagrees that results in straw man.
An argument commits the fallacy of straw man if and only if its premises attempt to
undermine some view through misrepresenting what that view actually is.
Situations where this type of informal fallacy often occurs include deliberations, such as de
bates and controversies. Straw man is (regrettably) a common tactic in public life, often heard
in the rhetoric of political campaigns. Typically, the straw-man argument ascribes to an oppo
nent some views that are in fact a distortion of his actual views. These misrepresentations may
be extreme, irresponsible, or even silly views that are easy to defeat. The opponent's position,
then, becomes a 'straw figure' that can be easily blown away. But to refute that position is of
z
LU
_J
LU
a:
a:
(.’) (/)
��
o-2
0 LU
> a:
I- Q
(/) 0
– <(
co _J
• _J
0 <(
� LI..
1-
z
<(
>
w
….I
w
er
er
0 (/)
��
o-�
ow
> er
<( 0..
Will
would be inappropriate, even crazy, to be too rational. Think of falling in love, for instance, or
expressing affection toward one's parents, or toward one's children. Sentiments and desires
are essential to any life that is recognizably human, and logical thinkers commit no fallacy
when they are moved in appropriate ways by emotion.
Exercises
1. What does it mean to say that an argument's premises are 'irrelevant' to its conclusion?
2. How is the fallacy of appeal to pity a fallacy of 'irrelevant premises'?
3. What is the fallacy of appeal to force?
4. What is the fallacy of appeal to emotion?
5. What is the bandwagon appeal? How does it differ from an appeal to vanity?
6. What is an ad hominem argument?
7. Do all ad hominems involve an attack on someone's character?
8. Are all ad hominem arguments fallacious? What is a tu quoque argument?
9. What is the beside-the-point fallacy?
10. What is a straw-man argument? And how does it amount to a fallacy?
II. For each of the following arguments, identify the fallacy of relevance it commits.
1. CBS News is trying to make people believe that there are unsafe working conditions in this factory.
But I tell you this: anyone who plans to continue working for me should not talk to reporters.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Appeal to force
*2. I deserve the highest grade, Professor Arroyo, because I studied harder than anyone else.
3. You cannot say that divorce is immoral. After all, you yourself are divorced.
*4. A Princeton student found guilty of plagiarism admitted that the work was not her own but argued
that the university ought not to penalize her for this infraction, since she had been 'under enormous
pressure at the time, having to meet a deadline for her senior thesis with only one day left to write the
paper.' -The New York Times, May 7, 1982
5. If Einstein's theory is right, then everything is relative. But 9-11 really happened, and that's a fact.
So not everything is relative. Therefore Einstein's theory is wrong.
6. We needn't take seriously what the Reverend Brimstone says when he tells us that people should
always be honest in their dealings with others. Just yesterday the Billy Brimstone Evangelistic
Association was found guilty of soliciting funds for missionary work and then using them to buy the
Reverend Brimstone a new Cadillac.
*7. Everywhere, people are increasingly getting rid of their iPods and instead listening to music on their
cell phones. That's the way to listen to music on the move! So, if you're up-to-date and in touch with
the latest things, you'll get rid of your iPod and use the phone to listen to music.
8. I know you're the coach of this baseball team, and you're entitled to your opinion. But I'm the owner
of this ball club, and you work for me. If you really want Scooter Wilensky to play third base, you can
put him there. Of course, I can always find another coach.
9. Everybody visits the Art Institute of Chicago. Therefore, you should, too.
*10. It's true that Knut Hamsun, the early twentieth-century Norwegian novelist, won the Nobel Prize for
Literature, but as far as I am concerned his works are worthless. Anyone who collaborated with the
Nazis, as Hamsun did during World War II, was not capable of producing works with literary merit.
11. A protestor demonstrating against the new president said, 'A recount of the ballots is needed in this
presidential election. If not, we will blockade airports and highways, we' ll take over embassies, and
we' ll bring traffic to a halt all over the country.'
12. People often point out that Richard Wagner, the nineteenth-century German composer of operas,
wrote some of the most beautiful and powerful music ever written . But I say all of his music is
worthless junk and should never be performed! It's well known that Wagner was a raving anti-Semite.
And decades after his death, his biggest fan turned out to be Hitler.
*13. In Britain, the president of the Royal Society has suggested that scientific research on how to protect
the environment should be supported by 'carbon taxes,' levied on countries producing the most air
and water pollution. But this is nonsense, for his own country would be near the top of the list, and
he himself drives a pollution-producing car!
14. The governor shouldn' t be blamed for his staff members lying under oath to the grand jury. After all,
he was under tremendous pressure at the time.
15. Humans are capable of creativity. Therefore, creativity is a value.
*16. Many contemporary physicists accept Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, which implies that
everything is indeterminate. But this cannot possibly be correct, as shown by the fact that
mathematical truths are determinate.
17. Professor Nathan's history of the Catholic Church is a classic. But she is a Protestant, so we cannot
expect her treatment of Catholicism to be fair.
18. In his dialogue Meno, Plato describes an exchange between Socrates and Anytus, a powerful and
influential Athenian politician. Socrates suggests that the reason why the sons of prominent Athenian
families often turn out badly is that their parents do not know how to educate them. To this, Anytus
replies, 'Socrates, I think that you are too ready to speak evil of men; and, if you will take my advice,
I would advise you to be careful. Perhaps there is no city in which it is not easier to do men harm than
to do them good, and this is certainly the case at Athens, as I believe you know.'
*19. Over two million people die in the United States every year. Therefore, the United States is a
dangerous place to visit, and we should take our vacation elsewhere.
20. Reverend Armstrong urges us not to support the war, saying that violence is barbaric in all forms and
only breeds more violence in return. But his view should be rejected, since it amounts to arguing that
our nation's enemies are not bad guys at all, and that we should just surrender to them.
21. Paul Robeson's accomplishments as an actor and singer are overrated. Really, he was not good at
either. After all, he was well known to be pro-Communist and an admirer of Stalin.
*22. Global war is inevitable, for the cultures of East and West are radically different.
23. My opponent, Senator Snort, endorses the Supreme Court's view that prayer in public schools is a
violation of the First Amendment. But I say to you, what is this but an endorsement of atheism?
Senator Snort clearly thinks that people of faith have no place in today's America.
24. I know I've failed to pay my rent for the past three months, but if you evict me I'll have no place to go.
How can you throw me, an eighty-year-old grandmother, out onto the street?
(/)
>
<(
<(
z
0
l
o
�
UJ
0
1-
_J
<(
UJ
[l_
[l_
<( ('-•
UJ (/)
I:::>
I- Q
(/) 0
– <(
� ::J
0 <(
� LL
1-
z
w
_j
w
a:
a:
(.') Cf)
z
w
- Cf)
��
ow
> a:
0 a..
�
0
0
11.1 Argument as a Relation between Propositions
In this chapter and the next, we’ll return to a topic briefly addressed in Chapter 5: propositional
arguments. Here we’ll have a close look at propositions, the building blocks of propositional
arguments. Consider
1 1. If the Earth is a planet, then it moves.
2. If the Earth does not move, then it is not a planet.
(1) is a propositional argument because it consists entirely in the relation between the proposi
tions that make it up. Its premise and conclusion are compound propositions, which result
from logical connections established between two simple propositions: ‘The Earth is a planet’
and ‘The Earth moves.’ The connections ‘if … then … ‘ and ‘not’ are among the five types of
truth-functional connectives (or simply ‘connectives’) that we’ll study here-namely,
Truth-Functional Connectives
negation*
conjunction
disjunction
conditional
biconditional
Standard English Expression
notP
PandQ
either Por Q
if P,then Q
P if and only if Q
* As we’ll see, negation is called a ‘connective’ by courtesy.
Here we are using capital letters such as ‘P,’ •�• and ‘R’ as symbols or “dummies” for any propo
sition. We’ll use other capital letters from ‘A’ to ‘O’ to translate propositions in English into
symbols, reserving P through W to represent non-specific propositions. Whenever possible,
we’ll pick the first letter of a word inside the proposition that we are to represent in symbols,
preferably a noun if available. For example, ‘If the Earth is a planet, then it moves’ may be
represented as ‘If E, then M’-where
E
M
The Earth is a planet
The Earth moves
We’ll resort to the same chosen symbol every time the proposition it symbolizes occurs again.
And if we have already used a certain letter to stand for a different proposition, then a letter of
another word, preferably a noun, in the proposition in question will serve. The argument form
of example (1) may now be represented by replacing each proposition occurring in its premise
and conclusion with a propositional symbol in this way, while momentarily retaining the con
nective ‘if … then … ‘ in English. The resulting translation is
1 ‘ 1. If E, then M
2. If not M, then not E
Let’s now consider the following arguments with an eye toward translating their propositions
into symbols:
2 1. Ottawa is the capital of Canada.
2. It is not the case that Ottawa is not the capital of Canada.
3 1. Either Fido is in the house or he’s at the vet.
2. Fido is not in the house.
3. Fido is at the vet.
4 1. Jane works at the post office and Bob at the supermarket.
2. Bob works at the supermarket.
5 1. TV is amusing if and only if it features good comedies.
2. TV does not feature good comedies.
3. TV is not amusing.
Once we have translated the propositions into symbols, we obtain
2′ 1. 0
2. It is not the case that not 0
3′ 1. Either For E
2. NotF
3. E
4′ 1. J and B
2. B
5′ 1. A if and only if C
2. Not C
3. NotA
Although (2 1 ) through (s’) feature connectives, not all propositional argument forms do:
(6) doesn’t.
6 1. p
2. p
In ( 6), the propositional symbol ‘P’ stands for exactly the same proposition in the premise and in the
conclusion. Known as ‘identity,’ any argument with this form would of course be valid, since if its
premise were true, its conclusion could not be false. But this is not our present concern. Rather, in
this section we’ve considered propositional arguments and discovered that their premises and
conclusions often feature truth-functional connectives. So let’s now look more closely at these.
11.2 Simple and Compound Propositions
Any proposition that has at least one truth-functional connective is compound; otherwise, it is
simple. Consider
z
0
n.
0
0
z
(/)
<( z �Q n. I � in wO n. NO ....: a: � n. &ill (j) z 0 1- (j) 0 0.. 0 a: 0.. 0 z 🙂 0 0.. � 0 0 IIIEm 7 Celine Dion is a singer and Russell Crowe is an actor. This is a compound proposition, made up of the conjunction of two simple propositions, 8 Celine Dion is a singer. 9 Russell Crowe is an actor. Conjunction is one of the five truth-functional connectives that we'll consider here-together with negation, disjunction, material conditional, and material biconditional. For each connec tive, we'll introduce a symbol and provide a truth-value rule that will be used to determine the truth value of whatever compound proposition is created by applying that connective. Since the truth-value rule associated with each connective defines the connective, each of them is a 'truth-functional connective.' But for the most part, we'll refer to them simply as 'connectives.' Here is the picture that will emerge: BOX 1 ■ TRUTH-FUNCTIONAL CONNECTIVES Connective In English In Symbols Symbol's Name negation notP ~P tilde conjunction PandQ P•Q dot disjunction PorQ PvQ wedge conditional if Pthen Q P:J Q horseshoe bi conditional P if and only if Q P=Q triple bar Before turning to each of these connectives, notice that there is always one connective governing a compound proposition, called 'main connective.' By identifying the main connec tive, we determine what kind of compound proposition a given proposition is: a conjunction, a negation, a disjunction, etc. Obviously, in cases where a compound proposition contains more than one connective, it is crucial to be able to determine which connective is the main one. Negation Negation is a truth-functional connective standardly expressed in English by 'not,' and symbolized by'-', the tilde. Negation can affect one proposition by itself. Even so, we'll refer to it as a 'connective' by courtesy. In ordinary English, the expression for a negation may occur in any part of a statement. When a negation is added to a simple proposition, that proposition becomes compound. (10), which may be represented as (10') exemplifies this: 1 0 Russell Crowe is not an actor. 10' ~C Here the simple proposition that has become compound by adding a negation is 'Russell Crow is an actor.' In (10'), we've used the tilde to represent negation, and C for the simple proposition affected by it. When possible, we'll use the first letter of an important word occurring in the proposition we wish to represent in symbolic notation. Propositions affected by negation could also be themselves compound. For example, 11 It is false that both Mars and Jupiter have water. 12 It is not the case that Mary is not at the library. To represent propositions that are negations, the symbol for negation always precedes what is negated. (12) is the negation of 'Mary is not at the library,' which is already a negation. So we have a double negation: the negation of a proposition that's itself a negation, which we can represent by the propositional formula 12'~ ~ L Since the two negations cancel each other out, (12') is logically the same as 12" L Any proposition or propositional formula affected by a negation is a compound proposition. The 'truth-value rule' that defines negation, and can be used to determine the truth value of a proposition (or propositional formula) that's affected by that connective, is: A negation is true whenever the negated proposition is false. A negation is false whenever the negated proposition is true. When a proposition is the logical negation of another, the two could not both have the same truth value: where 'P' is true,'~ P' is false; where 'P' is false,'~ P' is true. For example, (11) above, which is true, is the negation of 'both Mars and Jupiter have water,' which is false. But (14) below is not the negation of (13), since both propositions are false. 13 All orthodontists are tall. 14 No orthodontists are tall. Now consider these: 15 Some orthodontists are not tall. 16 Some orthodontists are tall. (15) is the negation of (13), and (16) is the negation of (14), for those pairs could not have the same truth value. But propositions that are logically the same would have the same truth value. For example, if (17) is true, (18) is also true. 17 Lincoln was assassinated. 18 It is not the case that Lincoln was not assassinated. (18) is a case of double negation: it is the negation of 'Lincoln was not assassinated.' Notice that propositions featuring expressions such as 'it is not true that,' 'it is false that,' 'it never happened that' are commonly negations-as are some propositions containing prefixes such as 'in-,' 'un-,' and 'non-.' For example, 0 z :::::, 0 0. � 0 0 0 z (/) <( z �Q 0. I � in in 2i'. NO ,..: a: � 0. (/) z 0 f [/) 0 0.. 0 er: 0.. 0 z :J 0 0.. ::;;; 0 0 19 My right to vote is inalienable. Here 'inalienable' means 'not alienable.' (19) is logically the same as 19' My right to vote is not alienable. Similarly, since 'unmarried' means 'not married,' (20) and (20') are also logically the same: 20 Condoleezza Rice is unmarried. 20' It is not the case that Condoleezza Rice is married. But (21) is not a negation: 21 Unmarried couples are also eligible for the prize. Here 'unmarried' is not being used to deny the whole proposition. It affects only the word 'couples.' Finally, notice that although verbs such as 'miss,' 'violate,' 'fail,' and the like have a negative meaning, they need not be taken to express negations. Conjunction Conjunction is a compound proposition created by a truth-functional connective standardly expressed in English by 'and,' and in symbols by '• ', the dot. The connective for conjunction is always placed between two propositions, each of which called a 'conjunct.' Conjuncts may themselves be simple or compound propositions. Let's consider the conjunctions of some simple propositions: 22 Mount Everest is in Tibet and Mont Blanc is in France. 23 Mars and Jupiter have water. In symbols, these are 22' E • B 23' M •J Recall (11) above: 11 It is false that both Mars and Jupiter have water. The formula that represents this proposition is (11'), which has parentheses to indicate that both M and J are under the scope of the negation. 11 '-(M • J) We'll have more to say on the use of parentheses and other punctuation signs later. Now let's consider why conjunction is a truth-functional connective: because it determines the truth value of the compound proposition affected by it, given the values of its members and this truth-value rule: A conjunction is true if and only if its conjuncts are both true. Otherwise, a conjunction is false. (22) is true since both its conjuncts are in fact true. But if one conjunct is false and the other true, or both are false, then a conjunction is false. Thus (23) is false, since for all we know, both of its conjuncts are false. The following are also false: 24 Mount Everest is in Tibet and Mont Blanc is not in France. 25 Mount Everest is not in Tibet and Mont Blanc is not in France. Since Mont Blanc is in France, the second disjunct in (24) is false, which makes the conjunction false. In a conjunction, then, falsity is like an infection: if there's any at all, it corrupts the whole compound. (Logical thinkers who are contemplating a career in politics should keep this in mind!) In (25)1 both conjuncts are false, since each is the negation of a true proposition. In symbols: 24'E•-B 25'-E •-B Note also that, like (23), many conjunctions in ordinary language are abbreviated. For instance, 26 Rottweilers and Dobermans are fierce dogs. This is just a shortened way of saying 27 Rottweilers are fierce dogs and Dobermans are fierce dogs. Yet (28) is not short for a conjunction of two simple propositions, but is rather a single propo sition about a certain relation between some such dogs. 28 Some Rottweilers and Dobermans are barking at each other. Another thing to notice is that conjunction, as a truth-functional connective, is commutative that is, the order of the conjuncts doesn't affect the truth value of the compound. Assuming that (26) is true, the facts that make it true are exactly the same as those that make 'Dobermans are fierce dogs and Rottweilers are fierce dogs' true, which are also the same that make (27) true. However, we must be careful about this, since sometimes order matters. When it does, the conjunction is not a truth-functional connective: for example, 29 He took off his shoes and got into bed. The facts that make (29) true do not seem to be the same as those that make (30) true: 30 He got into bed and took off his shoes. The order of events, and therefore of the conjuncts, does matter in these non-truth-functional conjunctions-as it also does in (31) and (32). 0 z :::i 0 Q. 2 0 0 0 z (/) <( z �Q Q. 1- 2 U) -o (/) Q. (\J 0 ,...: a: � Q. (/) z 0 C- U) 0 0.. 0 a: 0.. 0 z :::, 0 0.. � 0 0 El 31 He saw her and said 'hello.' 32 He said 'hello' and saw her. Finally, note that besides 'and,' there are a number of English expressions for conjunction, including 'but,' 'however,' 'also', 'moreover,' 'yet,' 'while,' 'nevertheless,' 'even though,' and 'although.' Disjunction Disjunction, also a commutative connective, is a type of compound proposition created by the truth-functional connective standardly expressed in English by 'or,' and in symbols by 'v', the wedge. In representing a disjunction, the connective is placed between two propositions called 'disjuncts,' which may themselves be simple or compound propositions. Here are two disjunc tions, first in English and then in symbols: 33 Rome is in Italy or Rome is in Finland. 33' I v F 34 Rome is not in Italy or Paris is not in France. 34'-I v-F (33) and (34) are disjunctions and thus compound propositions. Disjunction is a truth functional connective because it determines the truth value of the compound proposition it creates on the basis of the values of its members and this truth-value rule: A disjunction is false if and only if its disjuncts are both false. Otherwise, a disjunction is true. Given the above rule, at least one of the disjuncts must be true for the disjunction to be true. So (33) is true, but (34) is false. (35) is also false, for both its disjuncts, both of them compound propositions, are false: 35 Either snow tires are useful in the tropics and air conditioners are popular in Iceland, or it is not the case that Penguins thrive in cold temperatures. 35' (S • A) v ~ P Clearly, the conjunction (S • A) is false because both conjuncts are false, and - P is false because it is the negation of P, which is true. Since both disjuncts in (35) are false, given the truth-value rule for disjunction, (35) is false. In addition to 'or,' disjunction can be expressed by 'either ... or ... ' and 'unless,' and other locutions of our language. It is also sometimes found embedded in a negation in 'neither ... nor ... '(where negation is the main connective). Thus these are also disjunctions: 36 She is the director of the project, unless the catalog is wrong. 36' Either she is the director of the project, or the catalog is wrong. (37) is a shortened version of (37'): 37 Neither the CIA nor the FBI tolerates terrorists. 37' Neither the CIA tolerates terrorists nor the FBI tolerates terrorists. Since 'neither ... nor ... ' is a common way to express the negation of a disjunction, (37) is log ically the same as (or equivalent to) 38 It is false that either the CIA tolerates terrorists or the FBI tolerates terrorists. Thus both (37) and (38) may be symbolized as the negation of a disjunction: 38'-(CvF ) Note that here the main connective is negation, not disjunction. Furthermore, (37) and (38) are logically equivalent to (39), which may be symbolized as 39 The CIA doesn't tolerate terrorists and the FBI doesn't tolerate terrorists. 39'- C • -F Finally, a truth-functional disjunction may be inclusive, when both disjuncts could be true ('either P or Qor both'), or exclusive, when only one could be ('either P or Qbut not both'). This book focuses on inclusive disjunction, whose truth-value rule is given above. Material Conditional Material conditional, a type of compound proposition also called 'material implication' or simply 'conditional,' is created by a truth-functional logical connective, standardly expressed in English by 'if ... then ... ,' and in symbols by '::)', the horseshoe. For example, 40 If Maria is a practicing attorney, then she has passed the bar exam. A conditional has two members: the proposition standardly preceded by 'if' is its antecedent, and the one that follows 'then,' its consequent. The conditional is a truth-functional connective because the value of the compound proposition it creates is determined by the truth value of the antecedent and consequent, together with this truth-value rule: A material conditional is false if and only if its antecedent is true and its consequent false. Otherwise, it is true. Thus any conditional with a true consequent is true, and any conditional with a false antecedent is true. The two propositions in a conditional, which may themselves be either simple or compound, stand in a hypothetical relationship, where neither antecedent nor consequent is being asserted independently. Does (40) assert that Maria is a practicing attorney? No. Does it 0 z ::::, 0 a. L 0 0 0 z (/) <( z ::j Q a. I L in -o (/) a. NO � er: � a.. (/) z 0 1- if) 0 Q. 0 a: Q. 0 z ::J 0 Q. � 0 0 claim that she has passed the bar exam? No. Rather, in any conditional, 'If P, then �• P and Q stand in a hypothetical relationship such that P's being true implies that Qis also true. To chal lenge a conditional, one has to show that its antecedent is true and its consequent false at once. Notice that sometimes the 'then' that often introduces the consequent of a conditional sen tence may be left out. Moreover, besides 'if ... then ... ,' many other linguistic expressions can be used in English to introduce one or the other part of a conditional sentence. Such expressions may precede that sentence's consequent, its antecedent, or both-as shown in the examples below, where double underlines mark the antecedent and single underlines the consequent: Maria has passed the bar exam, provided she is a practicing attorney. Supposing that Maria is a practicing attorney. she has passed the bar exam. On the assumption that Maria is a practicing attorney. she has passed the bar exam. Maria is a practicing attorney only if she has passed the bar exam. That Maria is a practicing attorney implies that she has passed the bar exam. We'll now translate these conditional sentences into our symbolic language, using 'M' to stand for 'Maria is a practicing attorney' and 'E' for 'Maria has passed the bar exam.' Our formula rep resenting any of these propositions has 'M' for the antecedent and 'E' for the consequent. It lists 'M' first, then the horseshoe symbol, and 'E' last: 40' M :J E Here the rule is: To translate a conditional sentence into the symbolic language, we must list its antecedent first and its consequent last, whether or not these two parts occur in the English sentence in that order. Let's now translate the conditionals below into the symbolic language using this glossary: N = The United States is a superpower I = China is a superpower C = China has agents operating in other countries 0 = The United States has agents operating in other countries 41 If China is a superpower, then China and the United States have agents operating in other countries. 41' I :J (C • 0) 42 It is not the case that if the United States has agents operating in other countries, then it is a superpower. 42' - (0 ::J N) 43 China has agents operating in other countries provided that the United States and China are superpowers. 43'(N • I) ::JC 44 If the United States doesn't have agents operating in other countries, then it is not a superpower. 44'- 0::J-N 45 That China has agents operating in other countries implies that either it is a super power or the United States is not a superpower. 45' C ::J (Iv -N) 46 If either the United States or China has agents operating in other countries, then neither the United States nor China is a superpower. 46' (0 v C) ::J -(Nv I) 47 If the United States is not a superpower, then it either has or doesn't have agents operating in other countries. 47' - N ::J (0 v -0) Note that 'P unless Q'. could also be translated as 'if not P, then Q' Thus 'China is a member of the UN unless it rejects the UN Charter' is equivalent to 'If China is not a member of the UN, then it rejects the UN Charter.' Necessary and Sufficient Conditions. In any material conditional, the antecedent expresses a sufficient condition for the consequent, and the consequent a necessary condition for the antecedent. Thus another way of saying 'If P, then Q'. is to say that P is sufficient for � and Q is necessary for P. A necessary condition of some proposition P's being true is some state of affairs without which P could not be true, but which is not enough all by itself to make P true. In (40), Maria's having passed the bar exam is a necessary condition of her being a practicing attorney (she could not be a practicing attorney if she had not passed it, though merely having passed doesn't guarantee that she's practicing). A sufficient condition of some proposition Q'.s being true is some state of affairs that is enough all by itself to make Q true, but which may not be the only way to make Q true. In (40 ), Maria's being a practicing attorney is sufficient for her having passed the bar exam (in the sense that the former guarantees the latter). In a material conditional ■ Its consequent is a necessary (but not sufficient) condition for the truth of its antecedent. ■ Its antecedent is a sufficient (though not a necessary) condition for the truth of its consequent. 0 z 🙂 0 CL � 0 () 0 z (/) <{ z �Q CL I � in -o (/) CL NO ,..: a: � CL fl€■ (/) z 0 t: (/) 0 Q_ 0 a: 0 z :::) 0 Q_ � 0 0 Material Biconditional A material biconditional is a type of compound proposition, also called 'material equiva lence,' or simply 'biconditional,' created by the truth-functional connective standardly expressed in English by 'if and only if,' and in symbols by '!!!!', the triple bar. Some other English expressions for the biconditional connective are 'just in case,' 'is equivalent to,' 'when and only when,' and the abbreviation 'iff.' Each of the two members of a biconditional could be either simple or compound. Here is a biconditional, in both English and symbols, made up of simple propositions: 48 Dr. Baxter is the college's president if and only if she is the college's chief executive officer. 48' B= 0 The truth value of the compound proposition the biconditional creates is determined by the truth value of its members, together with this truth-value rule: A material biconditional is true whenever its members have the same truth value that is, they are either both true or both false. Otherwise, a biconditional is false. Given this rule, for a biconditional proposition to be true, the propositions making it up must have the same truth value-that is, be both true or both false. When a biconditional's members have different truth values, the biconditional is false. (49) through (51) are false, for each features propositions with different truth values. 49 The Himalayas are a chain of mountains if and only if the Pope is the leader of the Anglican Church. 50 London is in England just in case Boston is in Bosnia. 51 Parrots are mammals if and only if cats are mammals. By contrast, the following biconditionals are all true because in each case its members have the same truth value: 52 Lincoln was assassinated if and only if Kennedy was assassinated. 53 Beijing is the capital of France just in case Bill Gates is poor. 54 That oaks are trees and tigers are felines are logically equivalent. In any biconditional, each member is both a necessary and a sufficient condition of the other. Thus in (48), Baxter's being the college's CEO is both a necessary and sufficient condition for her being the college's president, and her being the college's president is both a necessary and sufficient condition for her being the college's CEO. So a biconditional can be understood as a conjunction of two conditionals. Thus we can represent (52) in either of these ways: 52' L=K 52" (L :::l K) • (K :::l L) (5211 ) is the conjunction of two conditionals whose antecedent and consequent imply each other. That is why the material equivalence relation is called a 'biconditional,' and, obviously, this connective is commutative. BOX 2 ■ SUMMARY: COMPOUND PROPOSITIONS ■ Any proposition that is affected by a truth-functional connective is compound. Otherwise, it is simple. ■ The truth value of a compound proposition is determined by factoring in: (1) the truth values of its members, and (2) the truth-value rules associated with each connective affecting that proposition. ■ Negation is the only connective that can affect a single proposition. Exercises 1 . What is a compound proposition? 2. What are the five logical connectives? And what does it mean to say that they are truth-functional? 3. Besides 'and,' what are some other words used to express a conjunction? 4. Besides 'either ... or ... ,' what are some other words used to express a disjunction? 5. Besides 'if ... then ... ,' what are some other words used to express a conditional? 6. Besides 'if and only if,' what are some other words used to express a biconditional? 7. In a material conditional, which part is understood to present a necessary condition of the other? Which part is understood to present a sufficient condition of the other? 8. How could the biconditional be rephrased using other truth-functional connectives? II. For each of the following propositions, determine whether or not its main connective is a negation. Indicate double negation whenever appropriate. 1. Either London's air pollution is not at dangerous levels or San Francisco's isn't. SAMPLE ANSWER: Not a negation 2. It is false that London's air pollution is at dangerous levels. *3. San Francisco's air pollution is unhealthy. 4. It is not the case that Mexico City's air pollution is not harmful. 5. Non-dangerous levels of air pollution are rare in big cities. 6. Dangerous levels of air pollution are illegal. *7. Dangerous levels of air pollution violate the Kyoto Protocol. 8. It is not the case that dangerous levels of air pollution violate the Kyoto Protocol. 9. Dangerous levels of air pollution are not illegal. *10. Cleveland's air quality now reaches non-dangerous levels of pollution. 0 z ::) 0 Cl. � 0 0 z Cf) <( z ::J Q Cl. I � U) U) � NO .,..:. a: �o.. mll Cf) z 0 0 0.. 0 a: 0.. 0 z :J 0 0.. � 0 0 111m Ill. For each of the following propositions, determine whether or not its main connective is a conjunction. 1. Mexico City's air pollution is not harmful, but Houston's is. SAMPLE ANSWER: Conjunction 2. Dangerous levels of air pollution are illegal and unhealthy. 3. Chicago's air is polluted; however, Washington's is worse. *4. Rome's air is as unpolluted as Cleveland's. 5. In Toronto, air pollution is a fact of life; moreover, people are resigned to it in the summer. 6. New York's polluted air is often blown out to sea by westerly winds. *7. The Kyoto Protocol mandates steps to reduce air pollution, but the United States has not complied. 8. London's air pollution is not at dangerous levels; however, that's not the case in San Francisco. *9. Either Vancouver has low levels of air pollution or Montreal has dangerous levels of air pollution. 10. It is not the case that Canada is not a signatory of the Kyoto Protocol. IV. For each of the following propositions, determine whether or not its main connective is a disjunction. 1. Neither China nor North Korea is a signatory of the Kyoto Protocol. SAMPLE ANSWER: Not a disjunction *2. China and North Korea are not signatories of the Kyoto Protocol. 3. Either the United States complies with the Kyoto Protocol or it doesn't. 4. It is not the case that Mexico City's air pollution is either harmful or unhealthy. 5. Mexico City's air pollution is neither harmful nor unhealthy. *6. New York's polluted air blows either out to sea or north to Canada. 7. Dangerous levels of air pollution violate health laws as well as the Kyoto Protocol. *8. Dangerous levels of air pollution violate either the Kyoto Protocol or internal regulations. *9. San Francisco's air pollution is at dangerous levels unless there is fresh air blowing from the sea. 10. It is false that neither China nor North Korea is a signatory of the Kyoto Protocol. V. For each of the following propositions, determine whether or not its main connective is a material conditional. 1. If the United States and China sign the Kyoto Protocol, then the biggest polluters agree to comply. SAMPLE ANSWER: Conditional 2. That London's air pollution is not at dangerous levels implies that London is complying with the Kyoto Protocol. *3. Either Montreal has dangerous levels of air pollution or Rome does. 4. Mexico City's air is not harmful provided that Houston's air is healthy. *5. Chicago's air is unhealthy only if it has dangerous levels of pollutants . 6. Washington's air pollution is not a fact of life unless people are resigned to it. 7. That Canada has signed the Kyoto Protocol implies that Canada is willing to comply. *8. It is not the case that if London has dangerous levels of air pollution, the United Kingdom has not signed the Kyoto Protocol. 9. Either Mexico City has air pollution or if Houston has it, so does Vancouver. *10. That China has not signed the Kyoto Protocol implies that neither Canada nor the United Kingdom has signed it. VI. For each proposition in Exercise V that is a conditional, mark its antecedent with double underline and its consequent with single underline (*4, *7, and *10). 1. SAMPLE ANSWER: If The USA and China sign the Kyoto Protocol, then the biggest polluters agree to � VII. For each of the following propositions, determine whether or not its main connective is a material biconditional. 1. Only if Chicago has dangerous levels of air pollutants is its air unhealthy. SAMPLE ANSWER: Not a biconditional *2. China has signed the Kyoto Protocol if and only if North Korea has. 3. Washington's air pollution is a fact of life just in case people are resigned to it. 4. If London's air pollution is not at dangerous levels, the United Kingdom has signed the Kyoto Protocol. *5. Montreal has dangerous levels of air pollution if Rome does. *6. London's air pollution is at dangerous levels if and only if its air is unhealthy. 7. It is false both that Houston's air is harmful and that it is unhealthy when and only when it reaches dangerous levels of pollution. *8. Chicago's air is unhealthy just in case it has pollutants that are either dangerous or otherwise unhealthy. 9. Dangerous levels of air pollution violate the Kyoto Protocol if and only if they violate UN environmen tal regulations. 10. New York's air does not reach dangerous levels of pollution only if it is either blown out to sea by westerly winds or dispersed by thunderstorms . VIII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB In each of the following, a proposition is taken either to be or not to be a condition that's necessary, sufficient , or both for the truth of another proposition. Provide the correct representation of each using the propositional symbols in parentheses and connectives as needed. 0 z :::, 0 0.. � 0 0 0 z rJ) <( z :'.:j Q 0.. f � U) -o (f) 0.. NO ...: a: � 0.. (/) z 0 1- (/) 0 0.. 0 a: 0.. 0 z ::J 0 0.. L 0 0 11111m 1. 'The potato has nutrients' (0) is necessary and sufficient for 'The potato is nutritious' (N). SAMPLE ANSWER: (0 ::> N) · (N ::J 0) or 0 = N
2. ‘John hunts’ (J) is necessary for ‘John is a hunter’ (H).
*3. ‘This figure is an isosceles triangle’ (I) is a sufficient for ‘This figure is a triangle’ (F).
4. ‘Fluffy is a cat’ (C) is not a sufficient condition for ‘Fluffy is a feline’ (F).
5. ‘Mary is a sister’ (A) is necessary and sufficient for ‘Mary is a female sibling’ (F).
*6. ‘Laurence is not British’ (B) is not necessary for ‘Laurence is not European’ (E).
11.3 Propositional Formulas for
Compound Propositions
Punctuation Signs
As we have seen in some examples above, parentheses, brackets, and braces can be used to remove
ambiguity in formulas by indicating the scope of their logical connectives. When a compound
proposition is joined to a simple proposition or to another compound proposition by a logical
connective, parentheses are the first recourse for determining the scope of occurring connectives
if necessary. When the compound proposition is more complex, brackets may be needed, and for
even more complex compound propositions, braces. Thus parentheses are introduced first, then
brackets, and finally braces. For examples illustrating their correct use, see Box 3.
The compound proposition (P • Q} :::> R is a conditional, while P • (Q:::> R) is a conjunction.
Without brackets, the proposition (P • Q} :::> R v ~ S is ambiguous, since it is unclear which con
nective is its main connective: it admits of two different interpretations, one as a conditional,
the other as a disjunction. Finally, the main connective in ~ {[(P • Q} :::> R] v ~ S} is the negation
in the far left of this formula, which affects the whole formula. Compare ~ [(P • Q} :::> R] v ~ S.
Now, without braces, the scope of that negation is the conditional marked by brackets, and the
whole formula is not a negation but a disjunction.
Well-Formed Formulas
A formula representing a proposition, whether simple or compound, is well formed when it is
acceptable within the symbolic notation that we are now using. To determine whether a com
pound formula is well formed, the scope (or range) of its truth-functional connectives matters.
BOX 3 ■ PUNCTUATION SIGNS
parentheses ‘()’as in: (P • Q) :::> R
brackets ‘[]’as in [(P • Q) ::) R] v ~ S
braces ‘{}’as in: ~ {[(P • Q) ::) R] v ~ S}
Within the scope of negation falls the simple or compound proposition that follows it.
Negation is the only connective that has a single formula, simple or compound, within its
scope. For the other connectives, each has two formulas (simple or compound) within its
scope. Well-formed formulas (WFFs) often require punctuation signs to mark the scope of
their connectives.
Recall (52 11
) above, (L :::J .K) • (K:::, L), which is a well-formed formula with two conditionals
set inside parentheses to eliminate ambiguity: parentheses are needed here to indicate that
the compound proposition is a conjunction of two conditionals.
A different arrangement of punctuation signs could yield a different proposition even
when all propositional symbols remain the same, as shown by L :::, [K • (K :::, L)]. This is a
conditional featuring a simple proposition as antecedent and a compound consequent
that’s a conjunction of a simple proposition with another conditional (one made up of
simple propositions). If that conditional is false, we can say that by introducing negation
and braces in this way: – {L :::J [K • (K :::J L)]}. These are all WFFs, but the formulas in Box 4
are not.
BOX 4 ■ SOME FORMULAS NOT WELL FORMED
P-Q
P
PvQ•P
Symbolizing Compound Propositions
We’ll now have a closer look at some compound propositions. But first, consider
55 Fox News is on television.
Since there is no connective here, (55) is a simple proposition that we may symbolize as
55′ F
By contrast, (56), symbolized below as (561), has a negation and is therefore compound.
56 CBS News is not on television.
56′-C
Now consider (57), an abbreviated version of the longer proposition (57′):
57 Fox News is on television but CBS News is not.
57’ Fox News is on television but CBS News is not on television.
Either way, we have a compound proposition featuring two connectives: conjunction and
negation. The main connective, however, is the conjunction, whose scope is the entire
compound proposition. The scope of negation is only the second proposition. The underlying
principle for determining this is
a:
0
LL
(/)
T T F \;
y ��
VT
T
F
Exercises
1 . Why are punctuation signs part of the symbolic notation for propositions?
2. What’s the scope of a negation?
3. When Pis false and Q is true, what’s the value of P :::i Q?
4. Define P”” Q using only material conditional and conjunction.
a:
0
LL
(j”)
f-
0
UJ
z
z
0
0
(‘.J
z
z
w:
UJ (/) 0 UJ
«t:�
� <(
� f-
EDI
(/)
z
0
i==
in
0
n.
0
a:
n.
0
z
:::i
0
n.
�
0
0
IED
of the rule given in Box s to each row in the column on the left yields the results, recorded in
the column inside the box on the truth table's right-hand side. They are as follows:
First row: -Pis false when Pis true
Second row: -Pis true when Pis false
Other Truth-Functional Connectives. To define the other truth-functional connectives, first
we keep in mind that they involve two propositions, each of which could be T (true) or F (false).
This determines the number of Ts and Fs that we'll write on the column on the left-hand side
of the truth table. To calculate the total number of Ts and Fs in each column, we use the for
mula 2°
, where 2 stands for the two truth values a proposition may have (true or false) and n for
the number of propositions of different types that occur in the formula to which we'd apply the
procedure. In the definition of negation, there is only one proposition, so n is 1 and the for
mula 2
° produces two truth values: one T and one F. But, for conjunction, disjunction, condi
tional, and biconditional, each definition features two propositions, represented by P and Q. So
the formula is 2
2 and yields four places for the truth values of occurring propositions: two Ts
and two Fs. In the first column on the left, we assign half Ts followed by half Fs: that is, two Ts,
and two Fs (see truth tables below). In the other column on the same side of the truth table, we
assign four values in this way: T, F, T, F. On the top right-hand side of the table, have the for
mula whose truth value we wish to determine, and below it, the truth value resulting from the
application of the corresponding truth-value rule to each row of assigned values on the left.
The final result is marked by putting it inside a box and is obtained by applying the truth value
rule of each occurring connective to the values on the left-hand side of the truth table. Let's
now construct truth tables for each of the remaining types of compound propositions.
Conjunction. To define this connective with a truth table, keep in mind that
BOX 6 ■ TRUTH-VALUE RULE FOR CONJUNCTION
A conjunction is true if and only if its conjuncts are both true. Otherwise, a conjunction is false.
The truth table has two columns on the left, each of which assigns four truth values, two Ts and
two Fs, to each of its conjuncts. Its four horizontal rows are obtained by calculating the possi
ble combinations of those values while applying the rule in Box 6. The result, in a box on the
right, shows that a conjunction is true just in case the two conjuncts are true.
PQ
TT
T F
FT
F F
Disjunction. To define this connective with a truth table, keep in mind that
A disjunction is true if and only if at least one disjunct is true. Otherwise, a disjunction is false.
The truth table for disjunction has two columns on the left, each assigning four truth values,
two Ts and two Fs, to each of the disjuncts. Its four horizontal rows are the result of reading the
possible combinations of those values while applying the rule in Box 7. The final result, inside
the box in the right-hand column, amounts to a definition of disjunction: it shows that a
disjunction is true just in case at least one of its disjuncts is true. Equivalently, it defines
disjunction as a compound proposition that is false just in case both of its disjuncts are false.
p
TT
T F
FT
F F
PvQ
Material Conditional. To define this connective with a truth table, keep in mind that
BOX 8 ■ TRUTH-VALUE RULE FOR MATERIAL CONDITIONAL
A material conditional is false if and only if its antecedent is true and its consequent false.
Otherwise, a conditional is true.
As before, it has two columns on the left, each assigning four truth values, two Ts and two Fs,
to its antecedent and its consequent. Its four horizontal rows are obtained by calculating the
possible combinations of those values and applying the rule in Box 8. The result, inside the box
on the right-hand side, amounts to a definition of the material conditional. It shows that it is
true in all cases except when its antecedent is true and its consequent false.
p
TT
T F
FT
F F
Material Biconditional. To define this connective with a truth table, keep in mind that
BOX 9 ■ TRUTH-VALUE RULE FOR MATERIAL
BICONDITIONAL
A material biconditional is true if and only if both members have the same truth value.
Otherwise, a biconditional is false.
I
1-
:::J
a:
I
I-
�
(/)
UJ
>
i=
0
UJ
z
z
0
0
0
z
z
u..
UJ (/) 0 UJ
� a3
� <(
� I-
Cf)
z
0
1-
u.i
0
Q..
0
a:
Q..
0
z
::i
0
Q..
�
0
0
11111
This truth table has two columns on the left, each assigning four truth values (two Ts and two
Fs) to each simple proposition in the formula. Its four horizontal rows are obtained by
calculating the possible combinations of those values and applying the rule in Box 9. The truth
table's result appears inside the box on the right, and the truth table amounts to a definition of
the material biconditional. It shows that it is true just in case its two members have exactly the
same truth value: that is, they are either both true or both false.
PQ
TT
T F
FT
FF
P=Q
The five truth tables we've now constructed provide truth-functional definitions for each of
the five logical connectives. We can now use a similar procedure to determine the truth values
of other compound propositions.
11.5 Truth Tables for Compound Propositions
The truth value of compound propositions can be determined with truth tables. To construct a
truth table for a compound proposition, first identify the simple propositions in the formula
whose value you wish to check. Once you have written them down on the top of the left-hand side
of the truth table in the order that they appear in the formula, assign Ts and Fs in the way outlined
above, using 2n to calculate the total number of rows. For example, the truth table for F • - C is:
62 F C
--+-----
T T
T F
FT
F F
�
F
T
F
T
The formula on the right-hand side of this truth table is a conjunction of F, whose values we
read in the first column on the left, and - C, whose values we need to determine first. We do
this by applying the truth-value rule for negation to each row in the second column on the left.
Once we determine - C's values, we enter them under the tilde on the right. We then
determine the truth value of the conjunction by applying the truth-value rule for conjunction
to F's values (available on the left-hand side of the truth table) and- C's values (under the tilde).
We enter the values thus obtained under the dot, marking the resulting column with a box.
This column under the main connective is the most important one, because it provides infor
mation about the truth values of the compound proposition F • - C. It tells us that this com
pound proposition is true only when 'F' and '- C' are true (as shown in the second horizontal
row). On all other assignments of values, that proposition is false.
Now let's construct a truth table for
58' (H • M) ::) - B
The truth table for (58') is:
63 HMB (H • M) ::J -B
TTT T F F
TT F T T T
TFT F T F
TFF F T T
PTT F T F
FT F F T T
FFT F T F
FF F F T T
On its left-hand side, this truth table shows all possible combinations of truth values for the
three members of the compound proposition represented by the formula on its right-hand
side. That formula, whose truth value we want to determine, has three different simple
propositions symbolized by H, M, and B. As before, to calculate the number of rows needed,
we use the algorithm 2n, here 23, which reveals that eight rows are needed. Accordingly, we
assign Ts and Fs to the three columns on the left-beginning with the one farthest to the left
(the one under H), which has the top half Ts and the bottom half Fs-and continue to divide
that pattern in half as we move across to each of the two other columns to the right (under M
and B). This convention guarantees that we do get all possible combinations of truth values.
On the top line, it's all Ts, on the bottom line, it's all Fs, and in between are all other possible
arrangements.
Once we have entered these values, we look at the compound proposition formula on the
top right. It is a conditional, so the main connective is ':::>‘, under which we place the final
result (inside the box). But we can determine the possible truth values of the conditional only
after we first find the possible truth values of the antecedent, H • M, and the consequent, – B.
Those truth values make up the column under’•’ and the column under’-‘. The final step con
sists in applying the rule for the truth value of the conditional to those two columns.
BOX 10 ■ TRUTH TABLES FOR COMPOUND PROPOSITIONS
As we’ve seen, in a truth table, the number of truth values assigned to each simple proposition on
the left-hand side depends on how many different propositions occur in the formula at the top of
the right-hand side, whose truth value we wish to determine. For any simple proposition there are
only two possible truth values (true and false); therefore, for a compound proposition such as – P,
only two rows are needed. But with more propositions, the number of truth values would increase
according to the formula 2n : with two, it’s four lines; with three, it’s eight lines; with four, it’s
sixteen lines; and so on. In the case of (62), then, we need four lines. And, just to make sure that
we get all possible combinations of truth values, we’ll adopt this convention: in the column under
whatever letter symbol is farthest to the left, we put T in the top half of the rows and F in the
bottom half; and in the column under the other letter symbol to the right of that, we put a
sequence of alternating Ts and Fs.
0
z
🙂
0
Q.
�
0
0
a:
0
LL
(/J
w
_J
(l)
<( (/J
rz
IO
�E
a: (/)
rO
Q.
l{) 0
,..: a:
� Q.
(j)
z
0
E
0
Q_
0
a:
Q_
0
z
:::,
0
Q_
�
0
0
-
11.6 Logically Necessary and Logically
Contingent Propositions
Contingencies
What, then, have we learned about the truth values of the compound propositions on the
right-hand side of truth tables (62) and (63)? Just this: that each is neither necessarily true nor
necessarily false, but instead sometimes true and sometimes false, depending on the truth
values of the component simple propositions and the logical connectives. Propositions that
yield such truth values are contingencies. A compound proposition is a contingency if its truth
table displays at least one T and at least one F in the column under the main connective. In
(63), there is at least one T and at least one F under the ':::i'-and in (62), under the'•'. In light
of those results, each of these compound propositions is a contingency.
Contradictions
Contradictions are compound propositions that are always false, simply by virtue of their form
(and regardless of the actual truth values of their component simple propositions). In a truth
table for a contradiction, the column under the main connective symbol is all Fs. Consider
64 B =-B
Since (64) contains no proposition other than B, which occurs twice, the algorithm 21 yields two
places for truth values, one for T and the other for F. Accordingly, the truth table runs:
65 B B = -B ---+----
T
F
f"FlF
l!_JT
This truth table reveals (64) to be a contradiction.
Tautologies
Some propositions are tautologies: they are always true, simply by virtue of their form (and
regardless of the actual truth values of their component propositions). The truth table of a
tautology would have all Ts under the formula's main connective. The negation of (64) above is
a tautology, which reads,
66 -(B = - B)
The truth table for this proposition shows all Ts under the formula's main connective:
67 B -(B = - B)
--+-=----
; w
F F
FT
(67) gives the truth value of (66), thus confirming that it is a tautology. Among well-known
tautologies in logic are the so-called principles of excluded middle, P v - P, and non-contradiction,
-(P • -P). For further practice, check that these are tautologies by constructing a truth table for
each. Keep in mind that
BOX 11 ■ CONTRADICTIONS, TAUTOLOGIES, AND
NEGATION
The negation of a contradiction is a tautology, and the negation of a tautology is a contradiction.
Exercises
1 . How are truth tables used to define the five propositional connectives?
2. In a truth table for a compound proposition, how do we know how many horizontal rows are
required? What is the rationale for this?
3. In a truth table for a compound proposition, which column is the most important? And what does
that column tell us?
4. What is a tautology?
5. What is a contradiction?
6. What is a contingency?
XX. For each of the following formulas, construct a truth table to determine whether it
is a contingency, tautology, or contradiction.
1. W:J-K
SAMPLE ANSWER: Contingency
WK W :J -K
TT
TF
FT
FF
�F
T
F
T
2. (L v N) vA
*3. B :J (M :J B)
4. -J • (G vN)
*5. - [(A • B) :J (B • A))
6. D v (-M :J -0)
7. -[-(A • B) =(-Av -B)]
*8. (-A v-B) :J (B •A)
9. (F :J -N) • -(F :J -N)
*10. - A""+ K v -H)
11. (0 v M) :J (M V 0)
*12. -[(-A • H) v -(H :J -1)]
13. (E • -G) :J G
14.A "'-A
15. - (A = B) "' -L
*16. - {� • (8 • C)] = [(A • B) • Cl}
17. - {[(A • B) v (-B :J A)) :J B}
*18. (A • B)..,, (B • A)
19. (-B :J A)"" [(B v -0) :J CJ
*20. (A= B) = [(A :J B) • (B :J A)]
(/)
z
0
l-
o ui
zo
a: a:
*2. Earth is not the center of the universe or our planet is special. (E, 0)
3. Either our planet is special or it isn’t. (0)
*4. Earth is not the center of the universe just in case there is something special about our planet. (E, 0)
5. There is something special about our planet: however, Earth is not the center of the universe. (0, E)
6. It is false that either our planet is special or it isn’t. (0)
•7. If Earth is the center of the universe and there is something special about our planet, then there is
something special about our planet. (E, 0)
8. It is not the case that human life has value if and only if human life has value. (H)
9. Human life has a purpose, but it is not the case that it has value. (L, H)
10. Human life has value only if it has a purpose. (H, L)
*11. Human life has value and a purpose if and only if it is not false that human life does have value and a
purpose. (H, L)
*12. It is not the case that both Earth is the center of the universe and there is something special about
our planet just in case it is false that human life has value and a purpose. (E, 0, H, L)
13. Neither is Earth the center of the universe nor is there something special about our planet. (E, 0)
*14. Neither is Earth the center of the universe nor is there something special about our planet if and only
if both Earth is not the center of the universe and it is not the case that there is something special
about our planet. (E, 0)
15. Either human life has both value and a purpose or if it is false that there is something special about
our planet, then Earth is the center of the universe. (H, L, 0, E)
XXII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
Write down ordinary English sentences for each of the formulas below following this glossary: ‘F’ = Fred
is at the library; ‘M’ = Mary is at the library; ‘L’ = The library is open; ‘I’ = I have Internet access; ‘E’ =
The essay is due on Thursday.
SAMPLE ANSWER: 1. Mary is at the library but the library is not open.
2. F .. (L • M)
*3. F ss (L v – M)
4. (L • I) :::, (F v M)
*5. E”” (L:::, I)
■ Writing Project
6. (E • L) :::, (M v F)
*7. – [- F:::, (- L v M)]
8. (M • F) “” (E • L)
Find five compound propositions in English where the words used to translate the logical con
nectives don’t accord with the truth-value rules for those connectives. Write a short piece
arguing that the connectives in your examples are not truth-functional. Suggestions: look for
conjunctions that are not commutative, or ‘if … then … ‘ sentences where the consequent
appears not to be a necessary condition of the antecedent (e.g., ‘If I have money for bus fare
then I’ll take the bus’).
BOX 12 ■ SYMBOLIC NOTATION FOR PROPOSITIONS
Propositional Letters
From A to O for specific
propositions
From P to W for
unspecific ones
■ Chapter Summary
Connectives
~ negation
• conjuction
v disjunction
:::, Conditional
“‘ Biconditional
Punctuation Signs
( ) parentheses
I ] square brackets
{ } braces
Propositions: the building blocks of propositional arguments. Each proposition is either true
or false, and either simple or compound.
Compound proposition: any proposition whose truth value is in part determined by the
truth-value rule of one of the truth-functional connectives. It falls into one or another of
these categories:
1. Tautology. Always true, by virtue of its form. Its truth table shows only Ts under the main
connective.
2. Contradiction. Always false, by virtue of its form. Its truth table shows only Fs under the
main connective.
3. Contingency. Neither always true nor always false. Its truth table shows at least one T and
one F under the main connective.
Five Connectives and their truth-value rules:
1. Negation. True if and only if the proposition denied is false.
2. Conjunction. True if and only if its conjuncts are both true.
>
a:
<(
�
�
🙂
CJ)
a:
w
f-
0..
<(
I
()
Cl)
z
0
0
0
0
z
0
0
3. Disjunction. True if and only if at least one disjunct is true.
4. Conditional. False if and only if its antecedent is true and its consequent false.
5. Biconditional. True if and only if both members have the same truth value.
Truth Tables for the Connectives
Negation
; I�
Conjunction Disjunction
p Q p . Q PQ
TT
�
TT
TF TF
FT FT
F F FF
■ Key Words
Compound proposition
Negation
Conjunction
Disjunction
Material conditional
Antecedent
P vQ
�
Conditional Biconditional
p Q
TT
T F
FT
F F
p 🙂 Q PQ PaaaQ
�
TT
T F
FT
F F
Consequent
Material biconditional
Tautology
Contradiction
Contingency
�
CHAPTER
Checking the Validity
of Propositional
Arguments
In this chapter you'll learn some ways to determine whether propositional arguments
are valid or invalid. The topics will include
■ The use of truth tables in checking argument forms for validity.
■ Some standard valid argument forms in propositional logic: modus ponens, modus to/lens,
contraposition, hypothetical syllogism, and disjunctive syllogism.
■ The formal fallacies of affirming the consequent, denying the antecedent, and affirming a
disjunct.
■ An introduction to proofs of validity.
261
Cf)
LL f
Q Z
>– �
t:: :::i
g CJ
__J a:
<( <(
> __J
w <(
IZ
f- 0
CJ �
z
- Cf)
� 0
0 0...
WO I a:
0 0...
12.1 Checking Validity with Truth Tables
As we have seen, truth tables provide a procedure for determining whether a compound
proposition is a tautology, contradiction, or contingency. Moreover, they generate that outcome
in a mechanical way, applying certain rules that yield a result in a finite number of steps. But
they have another use that we'll explore at length here: they allow us to determine mechanically
whether an argument is valid or not. Consider, for example, this argument:
1 1. Either buffalo are prairie animals or coyotes are.
2. Buffalo are prairie animals.
3. Coyotes are not prairie animals.
To determine whether (1) is valid or not requires that we first obtain its argument form. We
translate (1)'s premises and conclusion into our standard symbolic notation and obtain:
1' 1.B vC
2.B
3. -C
Our next step is to transform this vertical listing of premises and conclusion into a horizontal
one, using commas to separate premises and writing the symbol ':. ', which reads 'therefore,'
in front of the conclusion. This gives us
1' B v C, B ... -C
We can now test this argument form for validity with a truth table. We enter the formula at
the top of the truth table on its right-hand side, and each different simple proposition that
occurs in that formula on the left-hand side. Next, we assign truth values to those simple
propositions, following the algorithm 2
n
, which for the formula under consideration is 2
2
(since the simple propositions occurring in it are two, B and C). Once this is done, we focus on
the smaller formulas that represent the argument's premises and conclusion, calculating
their truth values one at a time. These calculations are performed in the standard way
described in Chapter 11. In the final step, we check (in a way we'll presently explain) to see
whether the argument is valid or not. Our truth table for checking the validity of (1) above
looks like this:
2 B C
TT
T F
FT
FF
B v C, B :. -C
In (2), a value has been calculated for each formula representing the argument's premises and
conclusion. How? By reasoning as follows: the first premise is a disjunction, so its truth value is
calculated by applying the truth-value rule for disjunction to B and C, whose values have been
assigned on the left-hand side. The first column on the right, placed under the wedge, shows the
result of this calculation. Since the second premise, B, is a simple proposition, we cannot calculate
its values by using any of the truth-value rules for connectives. So we assign to B the same values
that we have assigned it in the first column on the left-hand side of the table. That is, we simply
transfer those values to the second column on the right-hand side of the table (this step can be
omitted, since B's values are readily available in the first column on the left, and could be read di
rectly from there). We then proceed to calculate the truth value of -C by applying the truth-value
rule for negation to the values of C, which are displayed in the second column on the left. We
write down the results of this calculation under the tilde, as shown by the truth table's third col
umn on the right. We're ready now to check whether the formula on its top right-hand side is a
valid argument form. To determine this, we scan horizontally each row displaying the values of B
v C, B, and - C (ignoring all vertical columns). We are looking for a row where the premises B v C
and B are both true and the conclusion - C false. And we do find precisely that in the first row.
This shows the argument represented by the formula to be invalid, since
If a truth table devised to test the validity of an argument displays at least one row
where premises are all true and conclusion false, that proves the invalidity of the
argument form tested.
BOX 1 ■ WHAT DO TRUTH TABLES HAVE TO
DO WITH VALIDITY?
The relation between validity and truth tables is simply this:
1. If it is possible for an argument to have all of its premises true and its conclusion false at
once-that is, if this occurs on one or more horizontal rows in its truth table-then the form
is invalid (as is any argument with that form).
2. But if this is not possible-that is, if its truth table shows no such row-then the form is valid.
(Recall that if an argument's form is such that it is possible for all of its premises to be true and its
conclusion false at once, then its premises do not entail its conclusion.)
The first row (indicated by an arrow) in the above truth table demonstrates the invalidity
of the form being tested (see rationale in Box 1). In this way we show that (1) is invalid. Similar
truth tables could be constructed to demonstrate the invalidity of any argument of the same
form. For example,
3 Either the media foster public awareness, or public opinion leads to public policy.
Since the media foster public awareness, it is not the case that public opinion leads to
public policy.
Since this argument has the same form as (1) above, the results of any correct truth table for
checking its validity would be exactly the same as those displayed in (2). (You should construct
such a truth table for your own practice.)
Let's now use a truth table to check the validity of another argument:
4 1. If Sally voted in the presidential election, then she is a citizen.
2. Sally is not a citizen.
3. Sally did not vote in the presidential election.
I
I-
>–
1-
0
_J
�
(9 (/)
� w
� _J
0 Ul
w <(
I 1-
0 I
� ::J
"" a:
� I-
EDI
(/)
LL 1-
0 Z w
>– 2
‘= ::)
0(9
::i a:
<( <(
> _J
w <(
Iz
I- 0
0 i==
z- (/)
�o
0 0...
WO
I a:
0 0...
111m
This has the form
4' M :J C,-C :. -M
First, notice that there are only two different simple propositions in this argument form, M
and C, each of which occurs twice. Thus we need only four assignments of values (two Ts and
two Fs) on the left-hand side of the truth table, and four horizontal rows. The next step is to
calculate the truth value of (4')'s premises and conclusion. Each of these is a compound propo
sition, for which we'll write the truth value in the column under its connective symbol: in the
first premise, under'::>‘, and in the second premise and conclusion under’-‘. In this argument
there are no simple propositions; to test for validity, therefore, we scan only the rows in
columns under the connectives: in the premises, these are the columns under the horseshoe
‘:::,’ and the tilde’-‘, and in the conclusion, it’s the column under the tilde’-‘. We’re looking for
a row in which all the premises are true and the conclusion false, which would indicate inva
lidity. But the scan shows that there is no such row in this truth table.
5 MC
T T
T F
F T
F F
The absence of such a row means that (4′), and therefore also (4), is valid. This test proves
validity because the truth table gives an exhaustive list of all possible combinations of truth
values of the premises and conclusion, and no horizontal row shows that the former can be
true and the latter false at once. Thus in all arguments with (4′)’s form, the premises entail the
conclusion. Consider these arguments:
6 If Professor Tina Hare is at the University of Liverpool, then she works in England.
Professor Tina Hare doesn’t work in England. Thus Professor Tina Hare is not at the
University of Liverpool.
7 If the Earth is not a planet, then Mars is not a planet. But Mars is a planet. Hence, the
Earth is a planet.
For your own practice, construct a truth table for these arguments to check their validity. You’ll
see that their final result will be exactly like that in (s) above.
Let’s try one more argument, this time more complex.
8 Since France is not a member of the union, it follows that Britain is not. For if France
is not a member, then either the Netherlands is or Britain is.
We can reconstruct (8) as
8’ 1. France is not a member of the union.
2. If France is not a member of the union, then either the Netherlands is a member
of the union or Britain is a member of the union.
3. Britain is not a member of the union.
which has the form
8″ -F, -F :J (N v B) :. -B
To test (8″) for validity, we first note that since three different simple propositions occur in it,
the truth table will need eight horizontal lines. Once we write down all possible combinations
of truth values for these simple propositions on the left-hand side of the truth table, we then
calculate the truth values of premises and conclusion and enter the results under each
connective symbol on the right-hand side. Here is the truth table, with the rows showing the
argument’s invalidity indicated by an arrow:
9 F NB -F, -F 🙂 (N v B) :. -B
TTT F F T T F
TTF F F T T T
TFT F F T T F
T FF F F T F T
FTT T T T T F +-
FT F T T T T T
FF T T T T T F
F F F I T F F I
The more complex formula on (9)’s right-hand side is the one representing the argument’s
second premise: it’s got three connectives in it. How do we determine which is the most
important? We do this by reading carefully and looking at the parentheses: they tell us that it is
the horseshoe placed between – F and (N v B). But in order to determine the truth values in the
column under the horseshoe, we first have to know the possible truth values of its antecedent, -F,
and its consequent, (N v B). Once we have the value of – F, which can be obtained by applying
the rule for the truth value of negation to F on the left-hand side of the truth table, we enter
those values under – F, the first premise of the argument (so they don’t need to be written twice
if desired). The value of (N v B) can be obtained by applying to the values of N and B the rule for
the truth value of the disjunction on the left-hand side of the truth table. To calculate the value
of – B, we proceed in a manner similar to that in which we calculated the values of – F. Once
this is done, then, ignoring all the other columns, we scan each horizontal row showing the
truth value for each premise and conclusion on the right-hand side of the truth table. We ask
ourselves: is there any horizontal row in which both premises are true and the conclusion false?
And the answer is Yes! It happens twice: on rows 5 and 7. Thus the argument form (8″) has been
proved invalid, and so any argument that has that argument form, such as (8) above, is invalid.
BOX 2 ■ HOW TO CHECK VALIDITY WITH TRUTH TABLES
■ When we use a truth table to check an argument’s validity, we first write the formula captur
ing the argument’s form at the top on the right.
■ Each different type of proposition that occurs in that formula goes at the top on the left.
■ The rows under the formula itself offer an exhaustive list of possible combinations of truth
values for premises and conclusion.
■ To decide whether an argument form is valid or not, we scan each row under the formula.
■ Any row showing that there is a configuration of truth values in which premises are true and
the conclusion false proves that the argument form is invalid.
■ If there is no such row, then the argument form is valid.
:r:
�
s
>
‘:::
0
_J
:;
(!) (/)
� UJ
:,t:: _J
o en
UJ <(
I�
o:r:
�
� ::J
<'i a:
��
(j)
LL f
Q Z
UJ
>– ::?:
I::: :::) 0 (9
::i a::
<( <(
> _J
UJ <( IZ f- 0 0 � z- (j) ::.:: 0 0 0.. wo I a:: 0 0.. IIIEI Exercises 1 . How do we construct a truth table to check the validity of a propositional argument? 2. How do we tell by a truth table whether an argument is valid or not? 3. Why is the truth-table technique a mechanical procedure for checking the validity of an argument? 4. If at least one row of a truth table for an argument shows all false premises and a true conclusion, is that relevant to determining the argument's validity? II. Use truth tables to determine whether each of these formulas represents a valid or an invalid argument. 1. H :::i -K , -K :. H SAMPLE ANSWER: Invalid HK H :::i -K, -K :. H TT F F F T F T T T FT T F F F F T T .I. 2. L v N, -N:.L 3. R :J (M :J R) :. M v R *4. J, J v N :. -N 5. -(B,., A) :J -L :. L :J (B ""A) 6. D v (-M :J -D) :. M :J D 7. -(G • E), -G :. E • -G *8. -C v -B, -(B • A) :. A v C 9. (F :J -N) • -(F :J -N) :. -N *10. -B, -(-K"" -H) :. K :J -H 11. (D v M) :::l (M v D) :. M v D 12. - [(-A• H) v (H :J -B)] :. -A• -H *13. K •(-Ev 0), -E :J -K :. 0 *14. E :J A, --A :. -Ev -A 15. A :J B :. -(-B :J -A) 16. -M v 0, M :. 0 17. A• B :. -A 18.C:JD:.D:JC 19. C :J D :. -C v D 20. C :J D, -C :. -D 21. A"" B :. (A :J B) • (B :J A) *22. H • (-1 v J), J :J -H :.J *23. - 0, A :::i B :. -0 • B 24. C :J D, D :. C 25. C :. C v D Ill. Translate each of the following arguments into symbolic notation. Then construct a truth table to determine whether it is valid or invalid. 1. Henry's running for mayor implies that Bart will not move to Cleveland, for if Henry runs for mayor then Jill will resign, and Jill's resigning implies that Bart will not move to Cleveland. (H, J, B) SAMPLE ANSWER: Valid HJ 8 H :::> J, J :::> -8 :. H :::> -8
TTT ,= FF FF
TTF T TT TT
TFT F T F F F
T FF F TT TT
FTT T F F TF
FTF T TT TT
FF T T T F TF
F F F .I .I T ..I T
2. If Quebec is a part of Canada, then some Canadians are voters. If Ontario is a part of Canada, then some
Canadians are voters. Hence, if Quebec is a part of Canada, then Ontario is a part of Canada. (8, C, 0)
*3. Algeria will not intervene politically if and only if Britain will not send economic aid. Thus Algeria will in
tervene politically unless France will not veto the treaty, for Britain will not send economic aid only if
France will veto the treaty. (A, B, F)
4. Neither Detroit nor Ann Arbor has cold weather in February. If Michigan sometimes has snow in
winter, then either Detroit or Ann Arbor has cold weather in February. Therefore, it is not the case that
Michigan sometimes has snow in winter. (D, A, M)
5. Either the examinations in this course are too easy or the students are extremely bright. In fact, the
students are extremely bright. From this it follows that the examinations in this course are not too
easy. (E, B)
*6. If John is a member of the Elks lodge, then either Sam used to work in Texas or Timothy is a police
officer. But it is not the case that Sam used to work in Texas, and Timothy is not a police officer.
Therefore, John is not a member of the Elks lodge. (J, A. I)
*7. Both antelopes and Rotarians are found in North America. But Rotarians are found in North America
if and only if French police rarely drink gin. It follows that if it is not the case that French police rarely
drink gin, then antelopes are not found in North America. (A, 0, F)
8. Dogs are not always loyal. For rattlesnakes are always to be avoided unless either dogs are always
loyal or cats sometimes behave strangely. (D, A. C)
9. If either Romans are not fast drivers or Nigeria does have a large population, then it is not the case that
both Nigeria does have a large population and Argentineans are coffee drinkers. Hence, Romans are
fast drivers, for Argentineans are coffee drinkers only if Nigeria does not have a large population. (F, N, A)
*10. We may infer that mandolins are easy to play but French horns are difficult instruments. For man
dolins are easy to play if and only if either didgeridoos are played only by men or French horns are
difficult instruments. But if French horns being difficult instruments implies that didgeridoos are not
played only by men, then it is not the case that mandolins are easy to play. (M, F, D)
11. If both Ellen is good at math and Mary is good at writing, then Cecil is a pest. It follows that Mary is
good at writing. For either Cecil is not a pest unless Mary is not good at writing, or both Ellen is not
good at math and Cecil is a pest. But Cecil is a pest if and only if Ellen is good at math. (E, M, C)
I
I-
>
I-
0
:::i
C) (/)
� UJ
� ….I
O CO
UJ <(
I 1-
0 I
� ::J
N a:
� I-
Cf)
LL 1--
Q Z
w
>– 2
!= ::) Oc,
:::::i a:
w
0 a:
<( (J)
02 z a:
�o
(J) l.l..
LU 1-
2 Z
0 LU (J)2 :::::,
(\J (9
Na:
� <(
(/) u..r-
0 di
>– �
‘= :J
0 CJ
:J a:
<( <(
> ..J w <( IZ
r- 0
CJ i==
z- (/)
-::t:
0 0 a.. wo I a:
0 a..
-
(14)'s form mirrors that of contraposition, since it is
14' 1. p ::J Q
2. -Q ::J -P
(14') helps us to see that (14) is a valid argument given that it has a valid argument form. Why is that
form valid? For similar reasons modus tollens is: since in the premise Q is the consequent of a
material conditional, it is a necessary condition for the truth of the conditional's antecedent P. Thus
if Q is false, then P must be false, too. The validity of contraposition is shown by this truth table:
15 P Q
TT
T F
FT
FF
p :::> Q :. -Q :::>-P
�
F
�
F
T FF
F TT
T TT
Hypothetical Syllogism
Hypothetical syllogism is labeled this way because it has two premises (that’s the ‘syllogism’ part) and
because its premises (as well as its conclusion) are hypothetical or conditional statements. Consider
16 1. If Elaine is a newspaper reporter, then she is a journalist.
2. If Elaine is a journalist, then she knows how to write.
3. If Elaine is a newspaper reporter, then she knows how to write.
This argument has the form
16 1
1. p ::J Q
2. Q ::JR
3. p ::J R
(161) allows us to see that (16) mirrors hypothetical syllogism, which is a valid argument form.
A closer look at this form reveals that premise i’s consequent is premise 2’s antecedent, and
premise i’s antecedent together with premise 2’s consequent are, respectively, the antecedent and
consequent of the conclusion. Obviously, since the antecedent of a conditional expresses a sufficient
condition for the truth of its consequent, when P is a sufficient condition for Q, and Q a sufficient
condition for R, it follows that P is a sufficient condition for R (16) is a substitution instance of this
form and is therefore valid. The following truth table shows the validity of hypothetical syllogism:
17 p Q R P::JQ Q::JR :. p ::J R
TTT T T T
TTF T F F
TFT F T T
T FF F T F
FTT T T T
FT F T F T
FF T T T T
F F F .I I I.
Disjunctive Syllogism
Finally, in our sample of valid argument forms, there is one that does not use conditionals at
all: disjunctive syllogism. The form is labeled this way because it has two premises (that’s the
‘syllogism’ part) and because one of its premises is a disjunction. Here, one premise presents a
disjunction, and the other denies one of the two disjuncts, from which the affirmation of the
other disjunct then follows as the conclusion. For example,
18 1. Either my car was towed away by the police or it was stolen.
2. My car was not towed away by the police.
3. My car was stolen.
(18) is a substitution instance of disjunctive syllogism, and as such may be correctly represented
in one of the two possible arrangements for the premises of that argument form, depending on
which disjunct is denied:
18a 1. p V Q
2.-P
3.Q
18b 1. p V Q
2.-Q
3. p
In the case of (18), since the negation affects the first disjunct of the disjunctive premise, the correct
representation is (18a). But the principle underlying either version of disjunctive syllogism is: given
the truth-functional definition of inclusive disjunction, if a premise that is an inclusive disjunction
is true but one of its disjuncts false, it follows that the other disjunct must be true. Thus any
argument mirroring (18a) or (18b) is valid-as demonstrated by this truth table:
19 P Q PvQ, -P :. Q
TT T F T
T F T F F
FT T T T
F F F T F
More Complex Instances of Valid Forms
When we set about trying to analyze propositional arguments, it’s immensely helpful to be
able to recognize these five basic valid argument forms, because any time you find an
argument that has one, you thereby know that it’s valid! No further procedure is required. For
the argument to be valid, it is enough that the general form of the argument’s premises and
conclusion mirror that of a valid form. This means that the premises and conclusion of a valid
argument could feature connectives other than those featured in the valid form mirrored by
that argument. That’s fine, provided that main connectives are exactly the same. Let’s make a
list including this and other considerations to keep in mind when deciding about the form of
propositional arguments:
#1. The order of the premises does not matter for an argument to have the form of a
modus ponens, modus tollens, hypothetical syllogism, or disjunctive syllogism.
#2. The English expression for a connective may be other than the standard one.
0
_…J
<( >
0
a:
<( (/) 0�
z a:
�o
(/) LL
w f
� z
ow
(/) � :J
N ('.)
C'i a:
� <(
(/)
LL 1-
Q Z
>– ‘.2
I:: 🙂
9 (.’J
…J a:
…J
w B
2. B :::> J
3. E :::> J
Now consider the following arguments, together with their correct representations:
24 1. Costa Rica is a peaceful country and doesn’t have an army.
2. Costa Rica is a peaceful country and doesn’t have an army only if it doesn’t have
public unrest.
3. Costa Rica doesn’t have public unrest.
24′ 1. C • -A
2. (C • -A) :::> -N
3. -N
25 1. Joey was either tried in Europe or extradited to the United States.
2. That Joey was either tried in Europe or extradited to the United States implies that
his defense failed and he is not free.
3. Joey’s defense failed and he is not free.
25′ 1. J v E
2. (J v E) :::> (D • -F)
3. D • -F
If we focus strictly on the main connective in premises and conclusions, then it’s clear that
both arguments turn out to be substitution instances of modus ponens. This is so because each
consists of a conditional premise (which happens to come second) and another premise that
asserts the antecedent of that conditional (which happens to come first). Neither the order of
these premises nor the fact that they themselves are compound propositions made up of several
connectives affects the status of the arguments as instances of modus ponens.
Exercises
1 . Explain the validity of modus ponens by reference to the necessary and sufficient conditions in a
material conditional.
0
…J
0
a:
I::::::>
Q0
_J er:
<( <(
> _J w <(
IZ
I- 0
0 �
z- (/)
� 0
0 Cl.
WO
I er:
0 Cl.
Mil•
2. Which sense of disjunction is required for disjunctive syllogism to be valid? Which of the valid forms
employs disjunction?
3. Suppose the order of the premises in a valid propositional argument is changed. Does that affect
the validity of the argument?
4. When you have established that an argument is a formal fallacy, what have you discovered about
that argument?
V. The following formulas are instances of modus ponens, modus to/lens, contra
position, hypothetical syllogism, or disjunctive syllogism. Say which is which.
1. A:) -B
A
-B
SAMPLE ANSWER: Modus ponens
2. (KvN)vA
-A
KvN
*3. L:) -M
B:) L
B:) -M
4. -(F • H)
A:) (F • H)
-A
*5. -E:) -D
-E
-D
*6. (A v LP (B • C)
-(B • C) 🙂 -(A v L)
7. -C v -A
A
-C
*8. (A • -F) 🙂 -G
G
-(A• -F)
9. J:) A
A:) -C
J:) -C
10. -H 🙂 -(Ev A)
(Ev A):) H
11. -B = C
( -B ""C):) -A
-A
*12.A v(G vF)
-(G VF)
A
13. A :J 0
-0:J-A
14. C vO
:£_
0
15. (G v F) :J A
(A :J 0):J (G v F)
(A :J 0) :J A
VI. The following arguments are instances of the valid forms discussed above.
Symbolize each and identify its form.
1 . Wynton Marsalis is an authority on music, for he is a famous jazz trumpeter who is equally well
known as a performer of classical music. But if he is a famous jazz trumpeter who is equally well
known as a performer of classical music, then Wynton Marsalis is an authority on music. (F, A)
SAMPLE ANSWER: F :J A, F .. A Modus ponens
2. Ernie is a liar or Ronald is not a liar. It is not the case that Ronald is not a liar. Therefore, Ernie is a liar. (E, L)
*3. If Staten Islanders are not Mets fans, then Manhattan's being full of fast talkers implies that Queens
is not the home of sober taxpayers. Thus if it is not the case that Manhattan's being full of fast talk
ers implies that Queens is not the home of sober taxpayers, then it is not the case that Staten
Islanders are not Mets fans. (I, M, H)
4. Penelope is not a registered Democrat. For Penelope is a registered Democrat only if she is eligible
to vote in the United States. But she is not eligible to vote in the United States. (D, E)
*5. If Democrats are always compassionate, then Republicans are always honest. For if Democrats
are always compassionate, then they sometimes vote for candidates who are moderates. But
if they sometimes vote for candidates who are moderates, then Republicans are always honest.
(D, M, H)
*6. If Emma is a true pacifist, then she is not a supporter of war. Emma is a true pacifist. It follows that
she is not a supporter of war. (E, A)
7. If this cheese was not made in Switzerland, then it's not real Emmentaler. Therefore, if it is real
Emmentaler, then it was made in Switzerland. (C, E)
*8. Either gulls sometimes fly inland or hyenas are not dangerous. But hyenas are dangerous. So, gulls
sometimes fly inland. (G, H)
9. If both Enriquez enters the race and Warshawsky resigns, then Bosworth will win the election. But if
Bosworth will win the election, then Mendes will not win the election. Thus if both Enriquez enters the
race and Warshawsky resigns, then Mendes will not win the election. (E, A, B, M)
*10. Microbes are not creating chronic diseases such as diabetes, multiple sclerosis, and even schizo
phrenia. Hospitals need to improve their cleaning practices only if it is the case that microbes are
0
_J
0
a:
<( U) 0 � z a:
�o
U) LL
w f
� z
ow
U) �
::J
N (')
N a:
� <(
(/)
LL t
Q Z
>– ‘.2
t: :::)
0 (.’)
:::::i a:
<( <(
> …J
w <(
IZ
t- 0
(.') j::
z_(/)
�o
0 0..
WO
I a:
0 0..
creating many chronic diseases such as diabetes, multiple sclerosis, and even schizophrenia. It
follows that hospitals need not improve their cleaning practices. (M, H)
11 . California farmers grow either vegetables that thrive in warm weather or citrus fruits and bananas.
Since they don't grow citrus fruits and bananas, they must grow vegetables that thrive in warm
weather. (A, C, B)
12. Steve's attacker was not a great white shark. An attack of the sort he suffered last week must be by
either a great white shark or by a shark of another type that felt threatened in the presence of a
swimmer unknowingly wading into its feeding area. Therefore, Steve was attacked by a shark of
another type that felt threatened in the presence of a swimmer unknowingly wading into its feeding
area. (G, A)
13. Calcium is good for healthy bones. Either vitamin D is good for healthy bones or calcium is not good.
Therefore, vitamin D is good for healthy bones. (C, D)
14. If herons wade either in mud holes or lagoons, then they catch bacterial infections. But they don't
catch bacterial infections. Thus herons wade in neither mud holes nor lagoons. (H, L, I)
15. If she has a tune stuck in her head, she is either happy or annoyed. Therefore, if she is neither happy
nor annoyed, then she doesn't have a tune stuck in her head. (H, A, N)
VII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. Construct an argument of your own for each of the argument forms listed in exercise M-
2. Construct truth tables for each of the argument forms listed in exercise (VI).
12.3 Some Standard Invalid Argument Forms
Already we have seen that arguments may have defects of various kinds that cause them to
fail. Types of defects that undermine arguments constitute the so-called fallacies, among
which, as we have already seen at some length, the informal fallacies figure prominently.
Now we must consider their analogues in propositional logic, which include some of the
formal fallacies.
All formal fallacies have in common that they occur in an argument that has a superficial
similarity to some valid form but departs from that form in some specifiable way. They are there
fore instances of failed deductive arguments. Recall that an argument is invalid if it is possible that
an argument with the same form could have true premises and a false conclusion. To prove the
invalidity of an argument, then, it is enough to find a single case of an argument with exactly the
same logical form whose premises are true and conclusion false. Consider the following argument:
26 1. If the messenger came, then the bell rang about noon.
2. The bell rang about noon.
3. The messenger came.
This argument is invalid because it is possible for its premises to be true and its conclusion
false. Even if the premises and conclusion all happen to be true in a certain case, there
are other scenarios in which arguments with an identical form could have true premises and
BOX 3 ■ INVALID ARGUMENT FORMS
['-___ s_o_M_ E_ F_O_R_ M_A _L_F _A_L_LA_C_I_E _s ___ ]
Either P orQ
p
AFFIRMING
A
DISJUCT
Either P or Q
Q
Therefore not Q Therefore not P
AFFIRMING THE CONSEQUENT
if P, then Q
Q
Therefor P
DENYING THE ANTECEDENT
if P, then Q
Not P
Therefore not Q
a false conclusion. Suppose that the messenger didn't come, but the bell did ring about
noon, though it was a neighbor who rang it. In this scenario, (26)'s premises are true
and its conclusion false. Thus the scenario amounts to a counterexample that shows the
invalidity of (26).
It is often possible to find real-life counterexamples that prove the invalidity of certain
arguments. Yet we could do without such counterexamples, since to show that an argument is
invalid, it is sufficient to describe a 'possible world' (which may or may not be the actual
world-it's simply a scenario involving no internal contradiction) where an argument with the
same form would have true premises and a false conclusion.
Thus the invalidity of an argument can be proved in the way just shown: one tries to
describe a scenario where the premises of the argument in question are true and its conclusion
is false. If such a scenario is not forthcoming, we may first extract the argument form-which,
in the case of (26), is
26' 1. p:) Q
2.Q
3. p
Then we try to find an example of an argument with the same form that in some possible
scenario would have true premises and a false conclusion. For example,
27 1. If Barack Obama is a Republican, then he is a member of a political party.
2. Barack Obama is a member of a political party.
3. Barack Obama is a Republican.
(27) shows that, in a scenario where the possible world is the actual world, an argument
with the same form as (27) has true premises and a false conclusion. By the definition of inva
lidity, (27) is invalid. At the same time, it amounts to a counterexample to any argument with
the same form.
0
__J
z
0
a:
t:::::)
Q0
_J a:
UJ
I::: :::J
0 (‘J
::i a:
<( <(
> _J
w <(
IZ
f- 0
('J i=
z_(f)
::,::: 0
0 CL
wo
I a:
0 CL
IElil
Affirming a Disjunct
Another formal fallacy is affirming a disjunct:
Affirming a disjunct is the fallacy committed by any argument featuring a premise that is an
inclusive disjunction, another premise affirming one of the disjuncts, and a conclusion denying
the other disjunct.
Affirming a disjunct is an invalid form because, as we saw earlier in our discussion of the
truth-functional connectives, 'or' is to be understood in the inclusive sense (i.e., either P or Q
or both)-not the exclusive sense (i.e., either P or Q but not both). The inclusive disjunction is
true in all cases except where both disjuncts are false. Thus assuming that a certain inclusive
disjunction is true, denying one disjunct (which amounts to saying that it is false) entails that
the other disjunct must be true. But affirming one of its disjuncts (which amounts to saying
that it is true) does not entail the denial of the other-that is, does not entail that the other is
false. (In the case of an exclusive disjunction, what we are calling 'affirming a disjunct' would
not be a fallacy.) Consider the following example:
32 1. Either my car was towed away by the police or was stolen.
2. My car was in fact towed away by the police.
3. My car was not stolen.
Is there any way this conclusion could be false if both premises were true? Yes! A possible
scenario is that thieves came in the night and broke into my car, then drove it to an illegal park
ing space, from which the police towed it! If that were the case, then both of (32)'s premises
would be true and its conclusion false at once. Thus the conclusion does not follow necessarily
from the premises-it is not entailed by them. So the argument is invalid. But the thing to
notice is that (32) instantiates version (a) of the invalid form affirming a disjunct. This fallacy is
committed by any argument of one of these forms:
32' a l. p V Q
2.P
3. -Q
b 1.PvQ
2. Q
3. -P
Since, here, the 'either ... or ... ' connective in (32) is inclusive, to affirm one of the two
alternatives does not entail a denial of the other. In any case where the disjunction is inclusive,
an argument with either of (32')'s forms is invalid. The invalidity of affirming a disjunct is
clearly shown by this truth table:
33 P Q PvQ, p
:. -Q
TT T T F
T F T T T
FT T F F
F F F F T
We have identified three invalid argument forms that correspond to three types of formal fallacy.
Whenever you find an argument that has one, a truth table is not required. All you need to do to
prove invalidity is simply to show that the argument has one of these forms: affirming the con
sequent, denying the antecedent, or affirming a disjunct. If you can keep separate in your mind
these three invalid forms and the five valid forms discussed earlier, you should find it much
easier to distinguish valid and invalid propositional arguments.
BOX 6 ■ HOW TO AVOID AFFIRMING A DISJUNCT
Note that in a disjunctive syllogism, a premise denies one of the disjuncts of the other premise,
and the conclusion asserts the other.
■ Thus, watch out for any argument that appears to be a disjunctive syllogism but it is not, since
one of its premises asserts a disjunct of the other premise, while its conclusion denies the other.
Exercises
YIII Review Ouestjons
1 . How does the type of disjunction at work in disjunctive syllogism bear on the fallacy of affirming a
disjunct?
2. How does affirming a disjunct differ from disjunctive syllogism?
3. How does affirming the consequent differ from modus ponens?
4. How does denying the antecedent differ from modus to/lens?
5. What's the cash value of recognizing that an argument commits a formal fallacy?
IX. Some of the following arguments commit formal fallacies, and some don't.
Indicate which do and which don't, identifying formal fallacies and valid argument
forms by name.
1. If the defendant's 2007 Toyota sedan was used as the getaway car in the robbery, then it was not in
the mechanic's garage with a cracked engine block on the date of the crime. But it was in the me
chanic's garage with a cracked engine block on that date! From this it follows that the defendant's
2007 Toyota sedan was not used as the getaway car in the robbery.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Modus to/lens. Valid.
2. If this car has faulty brakes, then it's dangerous to drive. But this car does not have faulty brakes.
Therefore it's not dangerous to drive.
*3. If our public officials take bribes, then there is corruption in our government. But if the mayor and
several City Council members were paid to support the appropriations bill, then our public officials
take bribes. So, if the mayor and several City Council members were paid to support the appropria
tions bill, then there is corruption in our government.
4. Barry is a union member, for he will not cross the picket line. And if he were a union member, then he
would not cross the picket line.
*5. Ireland does not allow abortion. Either Ireland allows abortion or Ireland is a conservative country.
Hence, Ireland is a conservative country.
0
_J
0
a:
<( (/) 0�
z a:
�o
(/) LL
w 1-
� z
0W
(/)�
:::>
(‘) 0
N cc
� <(
(/)
LL 1-
Q Z
>– :”!:
f:: ::J
0 (‘)
:J a:
w
t:::: ::)
9 (‘)
…J a:
<( <(
> …J
w <(
IZ
I- 0
(') i=
z-- (J)
� 0
0 a.
UJ 0
I a:
0 a.
ED
3. For each of the propositional arguments below, give its form and standard name (if any), use a truth
table to decide whether it is valid or not, and propose an argument of your own with exactly the
same form.
A.
B.
C.
D.
E.
F.
G.
H.
I.
J.
K.
L.
M.
If the cold front is here, then we don't go to the beach. Thus if we go the beach, then the cold
front is not here.
Either the small apples or the ripe ones are on sale. The ripe apples are on sale. Therefore, the
small apples are not on sale.
She is at Lalo's if her class is over. She is at Lalo's. Therefore, her class is over.
I don't see my glasses there. If I don't see them there, then they are not there. Hence, they are
not there.
If Ptolemy was right, then the Sun and planets orbit the Earth. But it is not the case that the Sun
and planets orbit the Earth. Therefore, Ptolemy was not right.
The ring is made of either gold or silver. In fact, it is not made of silver. Therefore, it is made of gold.
If the pool doesn't have chlorine, then it is not safe to swim in it. Since it is not safe to swim in it,
it follows that the pool doesn't have chlorine.
Irving is either a bachelor or he is a Dodgers fan. He is not a Dodgers fan. Therefore, he is a
bachelor.
If magnets cure rheumatism, then there is a market for them. But since it is not the case that
magnets cure rheumatism, there isn't a market for them.
There is a storm outside. If there is a storm outside, I'd better stay indoors. So, I'd better stay
indoors.
If Mary knows Juan, then she knows Jennifer. She knows Jennifer. Therefore she knows Juan.
Tokyo is the capital of either Japan or Bangladesh. Tokyo is not the capital of Japan. So Tokyo is
the capital of Bangladesh.
Customer Services handles complaints about merchandise that is either damaged or imperfect.
Customer Services handles complaints about merchandise that is damaged. Therefore,
Customer Services doesn't handle complaints about merchandise that is imperfect.
N. If the 'Big Bang' theory is not wrong, then the universe is expanding. The 'Big Bang' theory is not
wrong. Therefore the universe is expanding.
0. Either students who got As or those who have missed no class are eligible for the prize. Students
who have missed no class are eligible for the prize. So students who got As are not eligible for
the prize.
12.4 A Simplified Approach to Proofs of Validity
Some valid argument forms such as those discussed above are often used as basic rules of
inference in the so-called proofs of validity. This is a procedure designed to show the steps by
which the conclusion of a valid propositional argument follows from its premises. In
constructing a proof for an argument, we assume that it is in fact valid, and we try to show that
it is. Before we can proceed to construct some such proofs, we'll add other basic valid argument
forms and rules of replacement to our list so that we can have enough rules of inference to
prove the conclusions of a great number of valid propositional arguments.
The Basic Rules
In constructing our proofs of validity, then, we'll need some valid argument forms and some
logical equivalences between compound propositions. The former will serve as rules of inference,
which will permit us to draw a conclusion from a premise or premises. The latter will serve as rules
of replacement, which will permit us to substitute one expression for another that is logically
equivalent to it. Our list of rules includes the following:
Basic Rules of Inference
1. Modus Ponens (MP)
2. Modus Tollens (MT)
3. Hypothetical Syllogism (HS)
4. Disjunctive Syllogism (DS)
5. Simplification (Simp)
6. Conjunction (Conj)
7. Addition (Add)
Basic Rules of Replacement
8. Contraposition (Contr)
9. Double Negation (DN)
10. De Morgan's
Theorem (DeM)
11. Commutation (Com)
12. Definition of Material
Conditional (Cond)
13. Definitions of Material
Biconditional (Bicond)
What Is a Proof of Validity?
p :::> Q,P :. Q
p :::> Q, -Q :. -P
P :::> Q, Q :::> R :. P :J R
P V Q,-P :. Q
p. Q … p
P, Q :. p • Q
p ;. p V Q
(P :::> Q)=(-Q :::> -P)
P=–P
-(P • Q)=(-P v -Q)
-(P v Q) = (-P • -Q)
(P V Q) “”(Q VP)
(P • Q)=(Q • P)
(P :::> Q) = (-P v Q)
(P “” Q) = [(P :::> Q) • (Q :::> P)]
(P”” Q) = [(P • Q) v (-P • -Q)]
Proofs of validity may be formal or informal. In a formal proof, the relation of entailment is taken
to obtain strictly between certain well-formed formulas of a system of logic that need have no
interpretation in a natural language (such as English, Portuguese, Mandarin). Furthermore, the
basic rules of inference and replacement used in formal proofs are such that they could be used
to prove the conclusion of any valid propositional argument from its premises. On the other
hand, in the informal proofs proposed here, entailment is taken to be a relation that obtains
between certain propositions that are expressible in a natural language. When a proof is offered
as involving only formulas, it is assumed in the informal approach that these have an
interpretation in a natural language. Moreover, the basic rules offered in our informal approach
fall short of allowing proofs of validity for any valid propositional argument.
I
0
<(
a: >
Q_ r
Q_ –
<( 9 ....J
0 <(
� >
U.. LL
:::::i 0
Q_ (/)
::2′ LL
-o
(/) 0
<( a:
'
‘= ::J
0 <.'J
::i er:
<( <(
> …J
w <(
IZ
I- 0
<.'J �
z- (/)
:,C:Q
0 Q..
wo
I CI:
0 D..
-
We'll construct proofs to check the validity of certain arguments and assume that those
arguments have an interpretation in English-even though for convenience's sake they may
be offered only in the symbolic notation. For valid arguments that are expressed in English,
we'll first translate them into the symbolic notation. Then we'll proceed to prove their valid
ity by using the rules listed above in a way that we'll explain shortly. These rules can be used
to demonstrate the validity of many propositional arguments, and we'll next see just how
this is done.
Whether in a formal or informal approach, all proofs of validity require that we assume
that, for any valid argument, it must in principle be possible to show its validity by the proof
procedure, which shows that a valid argument's conclusion follows from its premises once we
apply to those premises one or more basic rules of inference and/or replacement. Such rules
are 'basic' in the sense of being accepted without a proof. (Since any proof at all within this
system would assume at least some of them, there are basic rules that cannot be proved within
the system.)
How to Construct a Proof of Validity
Let's now put our basic rules to work and demonstrate the validity of the following
argument:
34 Both Alice and Caroline will graduate next year. But if Caroline will graduate next
year, then Giselle will win a scholarship if and only if Alice will graduate next year. So,
either Giselle will win a scholarship if and only if Alice will graduate next year, or
Helen will be valedictorian.
First, we translate the argument into the symbolic notation as follows:
34' A• C, C:::) (G = A):.(G = A) v H
We can now prove that this argument's conclusion, (G = A) v H, follows from its premises.
How? By showing that such a conclusion can be deduced from (34')'s premises by applying to
them only basic rules of inference and replacement. Our proof, whose four steps (numbered
3
1
4
1
5, and 6) aim at deducing the intended conclusion from (34')'s premises, runs
3411 1.A•C
2. C:::) (G =A)
3. C • A
4.C
5. G=A
6.( G=A) v H
:.( G=A) vH
from 1 by Com
from 3 by Simp
from 2 and 4 by MP
from 5 by Add
In line 3
1
we deduce C•A by applying commutation (see Com in the rules above) to premise
1. Any time we deduce a formula, we justify what we've done on the right-hand side of the
proof. In this example, the justification includes expressions such as 'from,' 'and,' and 'by' that
we'll later omit ('from') or replace by punctuation marks ('and' and 'by'). Note that a proof 's
justification requires two things: (a) that we state the premise number to which a certain rule
was applied (if more than one, we write down the premises' numbers in the order in which
the rule was applied to them), and (b) that we state the name of the rule applied. After justify
ing how a formula was deduced from the premise/s of an argument, that formula can be
counted as a new premise listed with its own line number. Since C • A in line 3 has been
deduced from the argument's premises, it is now a premise that can be used in further steps
of the proof. In fact, it is used in line 4 to deduce C in the way indicated on the right-hand
side of that line. Premises 2 and 4 allow us to deduce G = A in line 5, which follows from them
by modus ponens (MP). In line 6, addition (Add) allows us to deduce the formula that proves
(34)'s validity: namely, the conclusion of that argument. We have thus shown that its
conclusion follows from its premises, and we have done so by showing that it can be obtained
by applying only basic rules of inference and replacement to those premises. Thus (34) has
been proved valid.
Proofs vs. Truth Tables
As we've seen, in the case of truth tables, the truth values of an argument's premises and
conclusion are assigned according to rules associated with the truth-functional connectives
involved in that argument. Although here we've defined only five such connectives, their total
number is in fact sixteen. This is a fixed number. By contrast, the actual number of valid
argument forms and logically equivalent expressions that could be used to construct proofs of
validity may vary from one deductive system to another. Furthermore, the proof procedure
allows for no fixed number of steps to correctly deduce an argument's conclusion from its
premises: it often depends on which premises and basic rules we decide to use.
Since in these respects proofs permit a certain degree of flexibility, it is sometimes
possible, within a single system of basic rules, to construct more than one correct proof to
demonstrate the validity of a certain argument. That is, unlike a truth table, a proof is not a
mechanical procedure that always yields a result in the same way in a fixed number of steps.
Moreover, it might happen that, in constructing a proof for a certain valid argument, we err
in our assessment of its validity. We might simply "fail to see" at the moment that certain
rules can be put at the service of deducing that argument's conclusion from its premises and
mistakenly conclude that the argument is invalid. That's why we say that, for any valid
argument, one could 'in principle' construct a proof of its validity. It must be admitted,
however, that proofs do have one big advantage over truth tables: namely, that the latter tend
to be very long and unwieldy when an argument features propositions of many different
types. Proofs face no such problem.
Exercises
1 . In what does the method of proof consist?
2. Do proofs offer any advantage over truth tables?
3. What is a rule of inference?
4. How are rules of inference used in a proof?
5. What are rules of replacement?
6. In this section, a distinction has been drawn between a formal and an informal approach to proofs.
What is that distinction?
I
0
<(
a: >–
0… 1-
� e
0 <(
�>
LL LL
:::i 0
0… (/)
� LL
U) 0
<( �
""" 0...
C'.io
� I-
E1iill
(J)
LL f
Q Z
>– �
!:: ::::>
gc,
_J a:
w
2. -B
3. -A
4. -B v C
5. -A • ( -B v C)
2. 1. -D ::, -E
2. Ev~(/::, D)
3.1::, D
4. –(I::, D)
5.E
6. –E
7. –D
8.D
9. E • D
*3. 1. -D • C
2. F::, -C
3. -F::, (Ev D)
4. – -C::, -F
5. C ::, -F
6. C::, (Ev D)
7. C • -D
8.C
9. Ev D
10. D v E
4. 1. – A • (Av E)
2. -A
3. (Av E) • -A
4.AvE
5.E
6. Ev -E
*5. 1. (G ::, D) ::, -F
2. D ::, F
3. D • C
4. – F::, -D
5. (G ::, D) ::, -D
6.D
7. –D
8. -(G::, D)
6. 1. A ::, -(B ::, -D)
2. -(B ::, -D) ::, -D
/:.-A. ( -B V C)
1, 2 MT
2 Add
3, 4 Conj
/:.E • D
I:. D v E
I:. Ev -E
SAMPLE ANSWER
I:. -(G :J D)
3.D !:. ~A
4.A:::> ~D
5. –D
6.-A
•7. 1 . (D ::, C) v -(A v B)
2.A /;. -D V C
I
3. -(Av B) v (D ::, C)
4.AvB
a: >-
5. ~~(Av B) 0… I-
0… –
6. D::, C
LL LL
8. 1. (~D • C) • H I:. ~H v -D ::::i 0
0… (f)
2. ~D • C � LL
3. ~D
i7.i 0
2. – D :::>(A• B) !:. D v ~(D::, C)
3. ~(A• B) :::, -~D
4. (D :::> C) :::> –D
5. (D :::> C) :::> D
6. ~(D :::> C) v D
7. D v ~(D :::> C)
*11. 1. (~H v L) :::> ~(I • G)
2.G • I /:. -L • H
3.1 • G
4. –(I• G)
5. ~(~H v L)
6. ~~H • -L
7. H • ~L
8. ~L • H
12. 1. ( B :::> C) v ~A
2. -( B:::, C) vA I:. A= ( B::, C)
3. ( B:::, C):::, A
4. ~Av ( B:::, Cl
5. A:::, ( B :::> C)
6. [A :::, ( B :::, C)] • [( B :::, C) :::, A]
7.A=(B:::>C)
(/)
LL f-
0 dj
>- 2
I:: :::,
g C)
_J a:
<( <(
> _J
w <(
IZ
f- 0
C) �
z- (/)
� 0
0 [l_
wo
I a:
0 [l_
MIH
13. 1. ~A :J ( I v -0)
2. ~A• ~I
3. -A
4.1 v ~D
5. ~I• -A
6. ~I
7. -D
14. 1. E • [~I• (~D v I)]
2. [ ~I • (~D v I)] • E
3. ~I • (~D v I)
4. ~I
5. (-0 v I) • ~I
6. -D v I
7. ~D
8. -D v F
15. 1. E
2. Ev D
3. (Ev D) v C
4. C v (Ev D)
/:. ~D
I:. -D VF
!:. C v (Ev D)
XIV. Translate each of the following arguments into symbolic notation using the
propositional symbols within parentheses and construct a correct proof of
validity for it.
1. The Bensons and the Nelsons will be at the party. But if the Nelsons are at the party, then the
Finnegans will not be there. The Finnegans will be at the party only if the Bensons will not be there. It
follows that the Finnegans will not be at the party. (B, N, F)
SAMPLE ANSWER:
1. B • N
2. N :J -F
3. F :J -B
4. N • B
5.N
6. -F
!:. ~F
1 Com
4Simp
2, 5 MP
2. If elephants are mammals, then they are not warm-blooded creatures. It is not the case that
elephants are not warm-blooded creatures. From this we may infer that either elephants are not
mammals or they are not warm-blooded creatures. (E, C)
3. Either municipal bonds will not continue to be a good investment or stocks will be a wise choice for
the small investor at the present time. Municipal bonds will continue to be a good investment.
Therefore, stocks will be a wise choice for the small investor at the present time. (M, C)
*4. If Romania establishes a democracy, then Bulgaria will, too. Either Mongolia will not remain inde
pendent or Romania will not establish a democracy. Bulgaria will not establish a democracy, but
Romania will. Thus Mongolia will not remain independent. (D, B, M)
5. Zoe will not resign next week. For Keith will serve on the committee, and either Zoe will not resign next
week or Oliver will. But if Zoe does resign next week, then Keith will not serve on the committee. (K, E, 0)
*6. Honduras will support the treaty, but it is clear that either Russia will not support it or Japan will
support it. Japan supporting the treaty implies that Honduras will not support it. Therefore, Japan will
not support the treaty. (H, I, J)
7. If Macedonians and the Danes were polytheists, then most ancient Europeans also were. The Romans'
not being polytheists implies that both the Macedonians and the Danes were polytheists. It follows that
if most ancient Europeans were not polytheists, then the Romans were polytheists. (M, D, E, 0)
*8. Railroads are safe investments, but oil companies are not. It follows that oil companies are not safe
investments but public utilities are, because railroads are safe investments only if public utilities are,
too. (I, C, B)
9. Dramatists are not opinionated or historians are not disputatious. For if dramatists are opinionated,
then musicians are not good at math. But musicians are good at math. (D, M, H)
*10. Sicily is an island. Besides, if Italy is the home of famous soccer players, then Egypt is not the
birthplace of Caesar. In addition, if Italy is not the home of famous soccer players, then Norway being
full of tourists implies that Egypt is not the birthplace of Caesar. It follows that Sicily is an island, and
Egypt's being the birthplace of Caesar implies that if Norway is full of tourists, then Egypt is not the
birthplace of Caesar. (I, H, E, N)
■ Writing Project
Provide a hypothetical syllogism for the conclusion that if globalization is promoted, products
will be cheaper. Then offer a modus ponens for the conclusion that globalization entails fewer
American jobs. Compare the relative strength of these two arguments by discussing the
support for their premises. At the end of this discussion, reconstruct both arguments, marking
in each case premises and conclusion.
■ Chapter Summary
Procedures for determining whether an argument is valid:
1. Truth Tables: a mechanical technique that shows an argument form to be invalid if there
is a row where all premises are true and the conclusion false. Otherwise, it is valid.
2. Proofs: a nonmechanical technique that shows an argument to be valid if its conclusion can be
deduced by applying only valid rules of inference and replacement to the argument's premises.
Some valid forms. When an argument has any of these forms, it is valid:
1. Modus ponens
2. Modus tollens
3. Hypothetical Syllogism
4. Disjunctive Syllogism
5. Contraposition
p :J Q,P :. Q
p :J Q, -Q :. -P
P :J Q, Q :J R :. P :J R
P vQ,-P :. Q
p :J Q :. -Q :J -P
-Q :J -P :. p :J Q
>
a:
�
�
�
::)
Cf)
a:
w
f–
0..
�
I
0
(/)
LL 1-
0 Z
>- �
t:: :::>
g (‘.)
_J er:
<( <(
> _J
w <(
IZ
I- 0
('.) i=
z- (/)
::.:'. 0
0 0...
WO
I er:
0 0...
Some invalid forms. When an argument has any of these forms, it commits a formal fallacy
and is invalid:
1. Affirming the Consequent
2. Denying the Antecedent
3. Affirming a Disjunct
■ Key Words
Truth table for arguments
Modus ponens
Modus tollens
Contraposition
Hypothetical syllogism
Disjunctive syllogism
p:) Q 'Q :. p
p 🙂 Q '-P :. -Q
p V Q 'p ,', -Q
Formal fallacy
Affirming the consequent
Denying the antecedent
Affirming a disjunct
Counterexample
Proof of validity
CHAPTER
Categorical
Propositions and
Immediate Inferences
In this chapter you'll read about logical relations between categorical propositions,
which are the building blocks of syllogistic arguments. The topics include
Standard categorical propositions and the class relationships they represent.
Non-standard categorical propositions and their translation into standard categorical propositions.
How to represent categorical propositions in Venn diagrams and in traditional logic.
The Square of Opposition, both traditional and modern versions.
The problem of existential import.
Other immediate inferences from categorical propositions.
293
(f)
(f) Zw
Qo
f- z if) w
0 a:
0...
w
Q
LL
a: �
0... w
_J f
<( ::i:
00 -w
a: 2 0 ""' 0 == w
f- 0
<( z
0 <(
11&1
13.1 What Is a Categorical Proposition?
Categorical Propositions
Categorical propositions are propositions that represent relations of inclusion or exclusion
between classes of things, such as
1 All philosophers are wise persons.
2 No philosophers are wise persons.
Or between partial classes, such as
3 Some philosophers are wise persons.
Or between partial classes and whole classes, such as
4 Some philosophers are not wise persons.
The relationships between classes that matter for categorical propositions are, then, these
four:
■ Whole inclusion of one class inside another
■ Mutual, total exclusion between two classes
■ Partial inclusion, whereby part of one class is included inside another.
■ Partial exclusion, whereby part of one class is wholly excluded from another
In the above examples of categorical propositions, 'philosophers' is the subject term and 'wise
persons' the predicate term. These terms are the logical, rather than syntactical, subject and pred
icate of a categorical proposition. Each of them denotes a class of entities: that made up by all
and only the entities to which the term applies. Thus 'philosophers' denotes the class of philoso
phers and 'wise persons' the class of persons who are wise.
Categorical propositions (1) through (4) illustrate four ways in which the class of philosophers
and the class of wise persons can stand in relationships of inclusion or exclusion. Each of these
relationships may be represented in one of the following ways:
1 ' All philosophers are wise persons.
2' No philosophers are wise persons.
3' Some philosophers are wise persons.
4' Some philosophers are not wise persons.
Philosophers
X
In traditional logic, first developed in antiquity by Aristotle (384-322 BCE), the standard
notation to represent the logical form of categorical propositions is to use 'S' as a symbol for
any subject term, and 'P' for any predicate term. In that notation, then, the logical form of the
above categorical propositions is, respectively,
1. All Sare P
2. No Sare P
3. Some S are P
4. Some S are not P
In traditional logic, only statements that can be shown to have these logical forms qualify as
expressing a categorical proposition. Any such proposition always represents one of the four
relationships between classes mentioned above, which can now be described by using the
symbols 'S' and 'P,' which stand for the classes denoted by the proposition's subject and predicate.
Those relationships are as in Box 1. But we can also represent them by circle diagrams, in which
case we'd have
_J
<
0
er:
0
0
w
�
0
< C'-·
NO
C’i a:
� Q.
(/) (/) z UJ
Qo
f- z
– UJ
(/) a: 0 UJ
Q. LL
Oz
a: –
Q. UJ
_j �
4: –
00 – UJ
a: � 0�
CJ –
�o
4: z
0 4:
The Venn diagram representing (10) consists of two intersecting circles, one for the subject
term (‘U.S. citizens’) and the other for the predicate (‘voters’).
p
Since, according to (10), all members of the class denoted by its subject term are members of the
class denoted by its predicate term, the crescent-shaped part of S that has no members (i.e., that
representing U.S. citizens who are not voters) has been shaded out in the diagram. With the
Venn-diagram technique, shading a space means that that space is empty. Thus, in the above
diagram, S non-P is shaded out, to represent that there is nothing that is S that is non-P. This is
consistent with reading (10) as saying that the subclass of U.S. citizens who are not voters is an
empty subclass-or, equivalently, that there are no U.S. citizens who are not voters.
On the previous page, (1o)’s translation is provided, first, in the algebraic notation
introduced by the English mathematician George Boole (1815-1864), which reads, ‘S non-P
equals o,’ and then in the notation of traditional logic, reading ‘All S are P.’ What both say is
captured by the Venn diagram in the box: namely, that the subclass of S non-P (represented by
the shaded portion of the diagram) is empty.
Now let’s look at (11), an instance of the universal negative.
11 No U.S. citizens are voters.
p
Boolean Notation:
SP=o
E Proposition:
No Sare P
Since (11) is a universal proposition, its Venn diagram shows an empty subclass that has been
shaded out: the football-shaped center area, the intersection of’ S’ and ‘P,’ which represents the
U.S. citizens who are voters. The diagram thus captures that (11) denies that there are any such
voters: in other words, asserting (11) amounts to saying that the class of voting U.S. citizens has
no members. To the left of the diagram, (n)’s Boolean notation ‘S P = o’ tells us that the sub
class ‘S P’ is empty. Immediately below, we find (n)’s notation and type in traditional logic.
Keep in mind that, for any universal categorical proposition (whether affirmative or negative),
there will be a part of the circles shaded out, to indicate that that part has no members.
Next, consider the particular affirmative
12 Some U.S. citizens are voters.
Boolean Notation:
SP=#=o
I Proposition:
Some Sare P
p
This time, no universal claim is being made, but rather a particular one: a claim about part of a
class. As a result, the diagram shows no shading at all, but an ‘x’ instead, in the area where there
are some members. Since ‘some’ logically amounts to ‘at least one,’ (12) is equivalent to
12′ There is at least one U.S. citizen who is a voter.
Putting an ‘x’ in the football-shaped center space indicates that that space, ‘SP,’ is not empty
in effect, that it has some members (at least one). To the left of the diagram, we find (12)’s
Boolean translation’ SP=#= o,’ which tells us that the subclass ‘SP’ (i.e., the football-shaped area
in the center) is not empty-together with its type and notation in traditional logic.
Finally, what about a particular negative? Consider
13 Some U.S. citizens are not voters.
p
Boolean Notation:
SP=#=o
0 Proposition:
Some S are not P
__J
<(
0
a:
0
('J
w
I
<(
0
a:
0
LL
r/)
'.2
<(
a:
� r/)
-z
00
�E:
w r/)
>0
CL
NO
cry a:
� CL
(/) (/)
Zw
Qo
I- z -w
(/) a:
Ow
0.. u…
Oz a: –
0.. w
_J �
The two intersecting circles represent the two classes of things related in a categorical
proposition-the one on the left, the class denoted by its subject, the one on the right, the
class denoted by its predicate. The circles also determine four subclasses that we may
identify with the spaces drawn. The space in the center, where they overlap, represents the
subclass of things that are both Sand P at once (i.e., the subclass of things that are simulta
neously members of both classes), which is indicated by the notation ‘SP.’ The crescent
shaped space on the left represents the subclass of things that are S but not P, where the
negation is indicated by a bar over the symbol ‘P.’ The crescent-shaped space on the right
represents the subclass of things that are P but not S, where the negation is indicated by a
bar over the symbol ‘S.’ The space outside the two interlocking circles represents the class
of things that are neither S nor P. As we have seen, with these spaces we can use the Venn
diagram technique to represent the class inclusion and exclusion relationships described in
each of the four standard categorical propositions. To see how this works, let’s start with a
concrete example. Consider the four categorical propositions that may be constructed out
of ‘U.S. citizens’ as the subject term and ‘voters’ as the predicate term. All four relationships
of inclusion and exclusion between the class of U.S. citizens and the class of voters, as rep
resented in those propositions, are captured in the Venn diagram in Box 3. There we may
BOX 3 ■ VENN DIAGRAMS FOR CATEGORICAL
PROPOSITIONS
U.S. citizens
(S)
Nonvoting
Non-U.S. citizens
identify the following subclasses: (1) U.S. citizens who are voters, (2) U.S. citizens who are
not voters, (3) voters who are not U.S. citizens (which would include, for instance, those who
vote in other countries), and (4) non-U.S. citizen who are non-voters (which would include,
for instance, not only current citizens of other countries who do not vote, but also Henry
VIII, Julius Caesar, and even things like the Eiffel Tower, the Magna Carta, and the Grand
Canyon-in fact everything we can think of belongs to one or the other of these four possi
ble subclasses).
For each categorical proposition, then, there is a Venn diagram that shows the relation
ship of inclusion or exclusion that it involves. The bottom line is:
■ The areas displayed by a Venn diagram relevant to representing a categorical proposition
are three: those inside each intersecting circle and their intersection itself.
■ A Venn diagram for an A or E proposition shows a shaded area where there are no
members. No ‘x’ occurs in this diagram.
■ A Venn diagram for an I or O proposition shows an ‘x’ in the area where there are
members. No area is shaded in this diagram.
Exercises
1. In the previous section, Venn diagrams were used to represent categorical propositions. Explain
how this technique works.
2. What do Venn diagrams for universal propositions have in common? What about those for particu
lar propositions?
3. What does it mean when spaces are shaded out in Venn diagrams for categorical propositions?
And what’s the meaning of an ‘x’ placed in one of the circles?
4. What do the two circles stand for in a Venn diagram for a categorical proposition?
0
0..
C\I 0
C’) a:
� 0..
mlll
(f) (f) z LU
Qo
f- z
– LU
(f) 0:
Q LU
Q_ LL
Oz
0: –
Q LU
__J !;;: <( -
(.) 0
- LU
0: 2 0
2 0_
LU
f- 0
<( z
0 <(
IX. Determine whether each Boolean notation for the diagram on the right is correct.
If it isn't, provide the correct one.
1.SP=O
SAMPLE ANSWER:
Incorrect. It should be:
p
S P,¢.0
2. S P¢c 0
p
*3. SP ¢c 0
s p
4. SP� 0
p
X. For each categorical proposition below, first identify its letter name and
traditional notation. Then select the correct Venn diagram and Boolean notation
for it from the following menu:
Venn Diagram
1
p
2
p
3
s p
4
p
_J
0..
NO
(‘) a:
� 0..
(f) (f) Zw
Qo
1- Z
-w
(f) a:
Ow
a… lJ…
Oz
a: –
a… w
…..I ……
<( �
00
-w
a: � 0
� (.'J -
w
...... 0
<( z
0 <(
(1) SP= 0 (2) SP= O
Boolean Notation
(3) SP :it: 0 (4) S P :it= 0
1. No Sumo wrestlers are men who wear small-size shirts.
SAMPLE ANSWER: E proposition; no Sare P. Venn Diagram 2, Boolean notation 1.
2. Some sports cars are very expensive machines.
*3. All llamas are bad-tempered animals.
4. Some grocers are not members of the Rotary Club.
5. All waterfalls are places people in kayaks should avoid.
*6. No spiders are insects.
7. Some advertisers are artful deceivers.
8. Some cowboys are not rodeo riders.
*9. No atheists are churchgoers.
10. All oranges are citrus fruits.
11 . Some rivers that do not flow northward are not South American rivers.
*12. If a number is even, then it is not odd.
13. There are marathon runners who eat fried chicken.
14. Some accountants who are graduates of Ohio State are not owners of bicycles.
*15. Not all oils are good for you.
16. Some reference works are books that are not in the library.
17. If an architect is well known, then that architect has good taste.
*18. Nothing written by superstitious people is a reliable source.
19. Chiropractors who do not have a serious degree exist.
*20. Some resorts that are not in the Caribbean are popular tourist destinations.
13.3 The Square of Opposition
The Traditional Square of Opposition
Categorical propositions of the above four types were traditionally thought to bear logi
cal relations to each other that enable us to draw certain immediate inferences. These are
single-premise arguments, to some of which we'll turn now. We'll first look at the imme
diate inferences represented in the Traditional Square of Opposition, a figure that looks
like this:
BOX 4 11 TRADITIONAL SQUARE
OF OPPOSITION
(All Sare P) (No Sare P)
A CONTRARIETY E
s s
u u
B B
A A
L L
T T
E E
R R
N N
A A
T T
I I
0 0
N N
SUBCONTRARIETY 0
(Some S are P) (Some S are not P)
The relations represented in the Traditional Square of Opposition, which involve two
categorical propositions at a time, are as follows:
Relation
Contradiction
Contrariety
Subcontrariety
Subalternation
Established Between
A and O; E and I
AandE
I and 0
A and I; E and O
Let's now take up each of these relations in turn.
Name of Related Propositions
Contradictories
Contraries
Sub contraries
Superalterns: A and E
Subalterns: I and 0
Contradiction. Propositions of the types in diagonally opposite corners of the Square are
contradictories. Propositions that stand in the relation of contradiction cannot have the same
truth value: if one is true, then the other is false, and vice versa. Thus A and O propositions will
always have opposite truth values if their subjects and predicates are the same, as will proposi
tions of types E and I. Thus if (1) is true, (4) is false:
1 All philosophers are wise persons.
4 Some philosophers are not wise persons.
On the other hand, if (1) is false, then that's logically the same as saying that (4) is true.
Similarly, if it's true that
3 Some philosophers are wise persons,
(that is, there is at least one philosopher who is a wise person), then it is false that
2 No philosophers are wise persons.
z
0
(j)
0
n..
n..
0
LL
0
w
0:
a
(j)
w
f-
(j) (j)
Zw
Qo
f- z
And conversely, if (3) is false, then (2) is true. When we infer the truth value of a proposition
from that of its contradictory, as we've been doing here, we make a valid immediate inference:
a single-premise argument whose conclusion must be true if its premise also is. But contra
diction is only one sort of valid immediate inference according to traditional logicians; as we
shall see next, there are others.
BOX 5 ■ CONTRADICTION
in�
O w A and O ¢ <::i Contradictories
n_ LL
� � E and I ¢ <::i Contradictories
n. w
....J f-
< ::!'.
00
- w Contrariety, Subcontrariety, and Subalternation. The Traditional Square of Opposition also
a: �
g � includes the following logical relationships between propositions, which are valid given
� o certain assumptions that we'll discuss presently:
< z
O<
-
A and E ¢ Contrariety
I and 0 ¢ Subcontrariety
A and I ¢ Subalternation
Eand 0 ¢ Subalternation
Contrary propositions cannot both be true at once, but can both be false. For instance, by con
trariety, if (14) is true we can infer that (15) is false:
14 All bankers are cautious investors.
15 No bankers are cautious investors.
That's because these categorical propositions cannot both be true. Yet they could both be false
(as in fact they are).
But contrariety differs from subcontrariety, and neither of these is the same as contradiction.
Subcontrary propositions can both be true at once but cannot both be false. By subcontrariety, if
(16) is false, then (17) is true:
16 Some students are vegetarians.
17 Some students are not vegetarians.
These categorical propositions cannot both be false but could both be true (as in fact
they are).
Finally, there is the relationship of subalternation, which is a little more complex, since the
correct inference of truth values varies depending on whether we go from the universal
proposition to the corresponding particular, or the other way around. Logically speaking, to say
that an A proposition and the corresponding I proposition are in the relation of subalternation
is to say that if the A proposition is true, then the I proposition must be true, as well, but also
that if the I proposition is false, then the A must be false. And similarly, for an E proposition
and the corresponding 0, to say that they are in the relation of subalternation means that if the
E proposition is true, then necessarily the O proposition is true, but also that if the O is false,
then the E must be false as well. In either case, the universal proposition is called 'superaltern,'
and the particular of the same quality 'subaltern.' So
Subalternation is a logical relation between:
A and I (A superaltern, I subaltern)
E and O (E superaltern, 0 subaltern)
In this relation:
Truth transmits downward (from superaltern to subaltern)
Falsity transmits upward (from subaltern to superaltern)
Let's reason by subalternation as traditional logicians would. Suppose it's true that
18 All trombone players are musicians.
Then it must also be true that
19 Some trombone players are musicians.
This suggests that truth transmits downward. At the same time, since it is false that some
trombone players are not musicians, it follows that it is also false that no trombone players are
musicians-and this suggests that falsity transmits upward. But a false superaltern such as (14)
clearly fails to entail a false subaltern, since that some bankers are cautious investors is true.
14 All bankers are cautious investors.
And a true subaltern such as (17) fails to entail a true superaltern, since that no students are
vegetarians is false.
17 Some students are not vegetarians.
Truth-Value Rules and the Traditional Square of Opposition Let's now summarize all rela
tionships represented in the Traditional Square of Opposition, together with the rules to be
used for drawing immediate inferences from it:
Contradiction: Contradictory propositions cannot have the same truth value (if one is true, the
other must be false, and vice versa).
Contrariety: Contrary propositions cannot both be true at once, but can both be false.
Subcontrariety: Subcontrary propositions cannot both be false at once, but can both be true.
Subalternationfrom the superaltern to subaltern (i.e., from the universal proposition to the particu
lar proposition of the same quality):
If the superaltern is true, then the subaltern must be true.
If the superaltern is false, then the subaltern is undetermined
Subalternationfrom the subaltern to superaltern (i.e., from the particular proposition to the universal
proposition of the same quality):
If the subaltern is true, then the superaltern is undetermined.
If the subaltern is false, then the superaltern must be false.
z
0
1-
(j)
0
0...
0...
0
LI..
0
w
a:
a
(j)
w
I
I-
“.
(‘)
BIii
/J)
/J) Zw
Qo
f– z -w
/J) 0: Ow
Q._ LL
Oz
a: –
Q._ w
….J f-
<( ::;
00
-w
0: ::?: 0 "<;:
0 � w
f-- 0
<( z
0 <(
Given the relationships of contradiction, contrariety, subcontrariety, and subalternation repre
sented in the Traditional Square of Opposition, then assuming the truth values listed on the
left, we can infer the values listed on the right.
If A is true ¢ E is false, 0 is false, and I is true.
If A is false ¢ E is undetermined, 0 is true, and I is undetermined.
If Eis true ¢ A is false, I is false, and O is true.
If Eis false ¢ A is undetermined, I is true, and O is undetermined.
If I is true ¢ A is undetermined, E is false, and O is undetermined.
If I is false ¢ A is false, E is true, and O is true.
If O is true ¢ A is false, E is undetermined, and I is undetermined.
If O is false ¢ A is true, E is false, and I is true.
Existential Import
Although inferences by contrariety, subcontrariety, and subalternation are all licensed as valid
by the Traditional Square of Opposition, our ability to draw such inferences is undermined by
a significant difference between universal propositions, on the one hand, and particular
propositions, on the other: namely, that the latter (I and 0) have existential import while the
former (A and E) do not. That is, I and O propositions implicitly assume the existence of the
entities denoted by their subject terms. Since 'some' is logically the same as 'at least one,'
therefore an I proposition such as (20) is logically equivalent to (20'):
20 Some cats are felines.
20' There is at least one cat that is a feline.
Note that 'there is at least one cat ... ' amounts to 'cats exist.' Similarly, an O proposition such
as (21) is logically the same as (21'), which likewise presupposes that some cats exist:
21 Some cats are not felines.
21 ' There is at least one cat that is not a feline.
On the other hand, A and E propositions are logically the same as conditionals: (22) is equiva
lent to (22') and (23) to (23').
22 All cats are felines.
22' If anything is a cat, then it is a feline.
23 No cats are felines.
23' If anything is a cat, then it is not a feline.
Understood in this way, a universal categorical proposition doesn't have existential import,
since it is equivalent to a conditional, a compound proposition that is false if and only if its
antecedent is true and its consequent false. So (22') would be false if and only if there are cats
but they are not felines, as would (23') if there are cats but they are felines. If cats did not exist,
the antecedents of these conditionals would be false, and those conditionals true (independent
of the truth value of their consequents).
Thus the inference by contrariety is undermined: given this understanding of universal
propositions, contrary propositions could both be true in cases where their subjects are empty
(i.e., have no referents). Consider (24), which is equivalent to (241):
24 All unicorns are shy creatures.
24' If anything is a unicorn, then it is a shy creature.
Since nothing is a unicorn, (24')'s antecedent is false, and the whole conditional therefore true.
Now consider its contrary, (25), which is equivalent to (25'):
25 No unicorns are shy creatures.
25' If anything is a unicorn, then it is not a shy creature.
Here again, since nothing is a unicorn, (25')'s antecedent is false, and the whole conditional
therefore true. Clearly, then, (24) and (25) could both be true! It follows that, unless we assume
that the subject term of a true universal proposition is non-empty, we cannot infer that its con
trary is false.
Now, what about subcontrariety? This involves I and O propositions-which, in the modern
understanding, do have existential import. Although, given the Traditional Square of Opposition,
subcontraries cannot both be false, in the modern understanding they can. Consider now
26 Some unicorns are shy creatures.
This is equivalent to
26' There are unicorns and they are shy creatures.
Thus understood, (26) is false, since there are no unicorns. Compare
27 Some unicorns are not shy creatures.
This is equivalent to
27' There are unicorns and they are not shy creatures.
Since there are no unicorns, (27) turns out to be false as well. Thus (26) and (27) could both be
false at once. It follows that we cannot draw valid inferences by subcontrariety.
Finally, consider subalternation. From what we have just seen, this relation also begins to
look suspicious. How can one validly infer, for example, from an A proposition that has no
existential import, an I proposition that does? Of course, I-from-A and O-from-E inferences
might seem unproblematic at first, whenever the things denoted by their subject terms exist
for example, trombone players, accountants, and tigers. But when we're talking about entities
whose existence is questionable, inference by subalternation leads to absurdities, such as
28 1. All unicorns are shy creatures.
2. Some unicorns are shy creatures.
Since the conclusion in (28) is equivalent to (26') above, the argument appears to have "proved" that
unicorns exist! This attempt to draw a conclusion by subaltemation fails because it ignores the fact
that the premise has no existential import, while the conclusion (its subaltern) does have it.
z
0
r
(J)
0
Cl.
Cl.
0
LL
0
llJ
a:
<(
:::,
0
(J)
llJ
I
r
C')
C')
(/) (/) z lJJ
Qo
I- z
- lJJ
(/) a: 0 lJJ
Q_ u..
Oz
a: -
Q_ UJ
_J I
<{ �
00
- UJ
a: � 0
� CJ -
UJ
I- 0
<{ z
0 <{
IIE1D
The Modern Square of Opposition
Some qualifications of the allowable valid inferences according to the Square of Opposition
are needed to restrict the range of valid inferences involving categorical propositions. As
shown in Box 6, the Modern Square modifies the traditional one so that it leaves out the
relationships of subalternation, contrariety, and subcontrariety, retaining only contradiction as
a relation sanctioning valid immediate inferences. Contradiction holds between A and O and
between E and I propositions, which are in opposite corners of the Square, marked by the two
diagonals, as shown in Box 6.
From this Modern Square, we can see two things about a proposition and the negation of
its contradictory. First, they are logically equivalent: if the proposition in one corner is true,
then the negation of its contradictory must be true; and if the proposition in one corner is
false, then the negation of its contradictory must be false. Second, they entail each other: any
BOX 6 ■ MODERN SQUARE OF OPPOSITION
(All Sare P)
A
(Some S are P)
(No Sare P)
E
0
(Some S are not P)
inference from a proposition to the negation of its contradictory preserves truth value and is
therefore valid.
Here, then, is a complete list of the equivalences (and entailment relations) between a
proposition of one of the four standard types and the negation of its contradictory sanctioned
by the Modern Square of Opposition:
1. A= not 0
2. E= not I
3. I= not E
4. O= not A
So, given (1), if 'All oranges are citrus fruits' is true, then 'It is not the case that some
oranges are not citrus fruits' must be true; and vice versa. But given (4), if 'Some oranges are
not citrus fruits' is true, then 'All oranges are citrus fruits' must be false while 'It is not the
case that all oranges are citrus fruits' must be true. You should try, as an exercise, to run an
example for each of these equivalences. The bottom line is that for the listed propositions,
each pair have the same truth value: if one is true, the other must also be true; and if one is
false, the other must likewise be false. The former yields validity, the two combined logical
equivalence. Venn diagrams are consistent with the modern view of the Square of
Opposition. After all, it is only for particular propositions that we're required to use an 'x' to
indicate where there are members of the subject class (if they exist at all). Universal proposi
tions never require us to indicate where there are members, but only where there aren't any
(i.e., by shading).
BOX 7 ■ LOGICAL EQUIVALENCE AND VALIDITY
Logical Equivalence
When two propositions are logically equivalent, if one is true, then the other is also true; and if
one is false, then the other must be false as well. This is because the conditions under which they
are true or false are the same. Thus logically equivalent propositions have the same truth values:
they are either both true or both false. As a result, one of them could be substituted for the other
while preserving the truth value of the larger expression in which they occur, provided that nei
ther occurs in a special context that could not allow such substitutions. For example, a proposi
tion 'P' is logically equivalent to 'It is not the case that not P'; therefore, one can be replaced by the
other while preserving the truth value of the larger expression in which one of them occurs, pro
vided that, for instance, the expression does not occur inside quotation marks.
Validity
When two propositions are logically equivalent, if one is true, the other is true as well. This
satisfies the definition of entailment or valid argument: logically equivalent propositions entail
each other. Any argument from one to the other is valid.
Exercises
1 . What is an immediate inference?
2. Which immediate inferences are valid according to the Traditional Square of Opposition, and which
according to the Modern Square of Opposition? Support your answer with examples.
3. Subalternation works differently depending on whether it is an inference from superaltern to sub
altern or vice versa. Explain.
4. What does it mean to say that certain propositions have existential import? Which categorical
propositions have it, according to the modern interpretation of the Square of Opposition?
z
0
1-
(/)
0
Q_
Q_
0
LL
0
w
a:
<{
:::i
0
(/)
w
I
1-
(")
(")
E1III
(/) (/) z LlJ
Qo
I- z
-w
(/) a: 0 LlJ
a. u..
Oz a: -
a. LlJ
.J I
<( �
00
- LlJ
a: � o""'
0::::
I- 0
<( z
0 <(
XII. For each of the following, first name the type of the proposition related to it by
contrariety or subcontrariety, as the case may be, and state that proposition.
Then assume that the proposition given is true and determine the truth value of
its contrary or subcontrary.
1. All Icelanders are believers in elves.
SAMPLE ANSWER: E. Contrary. No Icelanders are believers in elves. False.
2. No epidemics are dangerous.
*3. Some humans are not mortal.
4. No riverboat gamblers are honest men .
*5. All labor unions are organizations dominated by politicians.
6. Some conservatory gardens are not places open to the public.
*7. Some lions are harmless.
8. No used-car dealers are people who can be trusted.
*9. Some bats are not nocturnal creatures.
10. Some historians are interested in the past.
XIII. For each of the propositions above, assume that it is false and determine the
truth value of its contrary or subcontrary. (*4, *6, *10)
SAMPLE ANSWER: 1. E. Contrary. Undetermined.
XIV. For each of the following, give the letter name of its contradictory and state that
proposition.
1. All bankers are fiscal conservatives.
SAMPLE ANSWER: 0. Some bankers are not fiscal conservatives.
*2. No Democrats are opponents of legalized abortion.
3. Some SUVs are vehicles that get good gas mileage.
*4. All professional athletes are highly paid sports heroes.
5. Some tropical parrots are not birds that are noisy and talkative.
*6. Some chipmunks are shy rodents.
7. No captains of industry are cheerful taxpayers.
*8. Some cartographers are amateur musicians.
9. All anarchists are opponents of civil authority.
*10. Some airlines are not profitable corporations.
XV. First suppose each categorical proposition listed in the previous exercise is true.
What could you then know about the truth value of its contradictory? Second,
suppose each proposition in the list is false. What could you then know about the
truth value of its contradictory?
XVI. For each of the following, first name the type of the proposition related to it by
subalternation and state that proposition. Then assume that the proposition
given is true and determine the truth value of its superaltern or subaltern.
1. Some westerns are not good movies.
SAMPLE ANSWER: E. Superaltern. No westerns are good movies. Undetermined.
2. Some string quartets are works by modern composers.
*3. No butterflies are vertebrates.
4. No parakeets are philosophy majors.
*5. Some comets are not frequent celestial events.
6. All Internal Revenue agents are hard workers.
*7. Some porcupines are not nocturnal animals.
8. Some Rotarians are pharmacists.
*9. No extraterrestrials are Republicans.
10. All amoebas are primitive creatures.
XVII. For each of the propositions above, assume that it is false and determine the
truth value of its superaltern or subaltern. (*4, *8, *10)
SAMPLE ANSWER: 1. E. Superaltern. False.
XVIII. For each proposition below, first give the letter names of all propositions related
to it according to the Traditional Square of Opposition, specify those
relationships, and state those propositions. Then, assuming that each proposition
listed below is true, what would be the truth values of the given propositions?
(Tip for in-class correction: Move clockwise through the relations in the Square.)
1. All tables are pieces of furniture.
SAMPLE ANSWER: E. Contrary. No tables are pieces of furniture. False.
0. Contradictory. Some tables are not pieces of furniture. False.
I. Subaltern. Some tables are pieces of furniture. True.
2. Some griffins are mythological beasts.
3. No liars are reliable sources.
*4. Some bassoonists are anarchists.
5. All trombone players are musicians.
z
0
f
(/)
0
a..
a..
0
0
w
a:
<(
::,
0
(/)
w
I
f-
C")
C")
(/) (/) z LI.J
Qo
1-- z
(/) LI.J
0 a:
0.. LI.J
0 LL
a: �
0.. LI.J
....J 1-
<( ::;
00
- LI.J
a: � 0� C)_ LI.J
1-- 0
<( z
0 <(
1111m
*6. No Americans are people who care about global warming.
7. All white horses are horses.
*8. All acts of cheating are acts that are wrong.
9. Some cyclists are not welcome in the Tour de France.
*10. Some things are things that are observable with the naked eye.
XIX. Assuming that the propositions listed in the previous exercise are false, what is
the truth value of each proposition related to them by the Traditional Square of
Opposition? (*3, *5, *7)
SAMPLE ANSWER: E. Contrary. No tables are pieces of furniture. Undetermined.
0. Contradictory. Some tables are not pieces of furniture. True.
I. Subaltern. Some tables are pieces of furniture. Undetermined.
XX. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. Assuming that the propositions listed in (XVIII) above are true, use the Modern Square of Opposition
to draw a valid inference from each of them.
SAMPLE ANSWER: All tables are pieces of furniture.
It is false that some tables are not pieces of furniture.
2. Consider propositions such as 'No centaur is a Freemason,' 'All hobbits live underground,' and 'Some
Cyclops are nearsighted.' What's the matter with them according to modern logicians? Explain.
*3. Determine which logical relation among those represented in the Traditional Square of Opposition
holds between premise and conclusion in each of the following arguments. Is the argument valid
according to the Modern Square of Opposition? Discuss.
A. All automobiles that are purchased from used-car dealers are good investments. Therefore,
some automobiles that are purchased from used-car dealers are good investments.
SAMPLE ANSWER: Subalternation. Invalid by the Modern Square.
B. Some residents of New York are dentists. Therefore, it is not true that no resident of New York is
a dentist.
*C. No boa constrictors are animals that are easy to carry on a bicycle. Therefore, it is false that boa
constrictors are animals that are easy to carry on a bicycle.
D. Some motorcycles that are made in Europe are not vehicles that are inexpensive to repair.
Therefore, it is not the case that all motorcycles that are made in Europe are vehicles that are inex
pensive to repair.
*E. It is false that some restaurants located in bus stations are places where one is likely to be
poisoned. Therefore, some restaurants located in bus stations are not places where one is
likely to be poisoned.
F. It is not the case that some politicians are not anarchists. Therefore, no politicians are anarchists.
*G. No pacifists are war supporters. Therefore, it is not true that some pacifists are war supporters.
13.4 Other Immediate Inferences
We'll now turn to three more types of immediate inference that can be validly drawn from
categorical propositions: conversion, obversion, and contraposition. In some cases, conversion
and contraposition allow an inference from a universal to a particular proposition, but the
validity of those inferences requires the assumption that the subject terms in the universal
premises do not refer to empty classes such as mermaids and square circles.
Conversion
Conversion allows us to infer, from a categorical proposition called the 'convertend,' another
proposition called its 'converse' by switching the former's subject and predicate terms while
retaining its original quantity and quality. Thus from an E proposition such as
29 No SUV is a sports car,
we can infer by conversion
29' No sports car is an SUV.
Here the convertend's subject and predicate terms have been switched, but its quantity and
quality remain the same: universal negative. The inference from (29) to (29') is valid: if (29) is
true, then (29') must be true as well (and vice versa). Similarly, by conversion, an I proposition
yields an I converse when the subject and predicates terms of the convertend are switched.
For example, the converse of (30) is (30'):
30 Some Republicans are journalists.
30' Some journalists are Republicans.
If (30) is true, then (30') must also be true and vice versa-so the inference is valid and the two
propositions are logically equivalent.
For A propositions, however, an inference by conversion in this straightforward way would
not be valid. For, clearly, (31 1 ) does not follow from (31):
31 All pigs are mammals.
31 ' All mammals are pigs.
Rather, an A proposition can be validly converted only 'by limitation-for (311
') does follow from (31)
31" Some mammals are pigs.
In such a case of conversion by limitation, the convertend's quantity has been limited in the
converse: the valid converse of an A proposition is an I proposition where the subject and
predicate terms have been switched and the universal quantifier 'all' replaced by the non
universal quantifier 'some.'
Finally, note that in the case of O propositions, there is no valid conversion at all. If we
tried to convert the true proposition (32), we'd get the false proposition (32').
32 Some precious stones are not emeralds.
32 Some emeralds are not precious stones.
(f) w
0
z
w
a:
w u..
z
w
0
w
2
2
a:
w
I
l
o
Ellllll
(j) (j)
Zw
Qo
f- z -w
(/) cc
Ow
Q.. LL
Oz cc -
a.. w
_j � <( -
00
-w cc � 0� C) -
w
f- 0
<( z
0 <(
This proves the invalidity of the inference from (32) to (32'). For any O proposition, an immediate
inference by 'conversion' commits the fallacy of illicit conversion, and the same fallacy is com
mitted when an A proposition is inferred by 'conversion' from another A proposition. To sum up,
here are the rules for conversion:
BOX 8 ■ CONVERSION
Convertend Converse Inference
A All Sare P Some Pare S (Valid by limitation only)
E No Sare P No Pare S VALID
I Some Sare P Some Pare S VALID
0 Some S are not P (No valid conversion)
Obversion
A categorical proposition's obverse is inferred by changing the proposition's quality (i.e., from
affirmative to negative, or negative to affirmative) and adding to its predicate the prefix 'non.'
The proposition deduced by obversion is called the 'obverse,' and that from which it was
deduced, the 'obvertend.' The inference is valid across the board. Thus from the A proposition
(33) it follows by obversion (33'):
33 All eagles are birds.
33' No eagles are non-birds.
From the E proposition (34), obversion yields (341):
34 No cell phones are elephants.
34' All cell phones are non-elephants.
The obverse of I proposition (35) is (35'):
35 Some Californians are surfers.
35' Some Californians are not non-surfers.
The obverse of O proposition (36) is (36'):
36 Some epidemics are not catastrophes.
36' Some epidemics are non-catastrophes.
In each of these, the obvertend's predicate has been replaced in the obverse proposition by the
predicate for its class complement, which is the class made up of everything outside of the
class in question. For instance, for the class of senators, the class complement is the class of
non-senators, which includes mayors, doctors, bricklayers, airplanes, butterflies, planets,
postage stamps, inert gases, and so forth .. . in fact, everything that is not a senator. The class
complement of the class of horses is non-horses, a similarly vast and diverse class of things.
For the class of diseases, the class complement is non-diseases. And so on. The expression that
denotes any such complement is a term complement.
BOX 9 ■ EQUIVALENCES AND NON-EQUIVALENCES
BY CONVERSION
All Sare P. All Pare S.
s p
NoSareP. NoPareS.
p
Some Sare P. Some PareS.
p
Some S are Some P are
�� �£
p
p
p
Unlike conversion, obversion is a valid immediate inference for all four types of categorical
proposition. For each of the four pairs of categorical propositions listed below, an immediate
inference from obvertend to obverse would be valid: if the obvertend is true, the obverse would
be true too. The following table summarizes how to draw such inferences correctly:
BOX 10 ■ OBVERSION
Obvertend Obverse Inference
A All Sare P No Sare non-P VALID
E No Sare P All Sare non-P VALID
I Some Sare P Some Sare not non-P VALID
0 Some S are not P Some Sare non-P VALID
w
0
z
w
a:
w
LL
�
w
0
w
�
�
a:
w
I
r-
0
(")
�
-
(J) (J)
Zw
Qo
f- z
U)W
0 a: Q_ w
0 LL
a: �
Q_ w
_J f-
<( �
00
-w
a: 2 0
2 0_
w
f- 0
<( z
0 <(
BOX 11 ■ EQUIVALENCES BY OBVERSION
All Sare P. No Sare
non-P.
s p
No Sare P. All Sare
non-P.
p
Some Sare P. Some Sare
not non-P.
p
Some S are Some Sare
not P. non-P.
Contraposition
s p
p
F
Contraposition allows us to infer a conclusion, the contrapositive, from another proposition by
preserving the latter's quality and quantity while switching its subject and predicate terms,
each preceded by the prefix 'non.' Thus the contrapositive of (37) is (37'):
37 All croissants are pastries.
37' All non-pastries are non-croissants.
Given contraposition, an A proposition of the form 'All S are P' is logically equivalent to
another A proposition of the form 'All non-P are non-S.' Recall that whenever two propositions
are logically equivalent, they have exactly the same truth value: if (37) is true, (37') is also true,
and if (37) is false, (37') must be false. And, as noted in Box 7 in the previous section, whenever
two propositions are logically equivalent, we may infer the one from the other: any such
inference would be valid. To visualize this relationship between (37) and (37'), you may want to
have a look at the corresponding Venn diagrams in Box 12 (think of' S' in the diagram as
standing for 'croissants' and 'P' for 'pastries').
BOX 12 ■ A'S EQUIVALENT AND E'S NON-EQUIVALENT
CONTRAPOSITIVES
All Sare P.
s
No Sare P.
p
p
All non-Pare
non-S.
No non-P
are non-S.
p
The contrapositive of an I proposition is another proposition of exactly the same quality and
quantity (that is, another I proposition), where the subject and predicate terms have been
switched and prefixed by 'non.' The contrapositive of (38) is (38'):
38 Some croissants are pastries.
38' Some non-pastries are non-croissants.
But (38) and (38') are not logically equivalent, as can be seen in the corresponding Venn
diagram in Box 12. Thus any inference drawn from one to the other by contraposition would
be invalid, an instance of the fallacy of illicit contraposition.
With E propositions there is also a danger of committing the fallacy of illicit contraposition.
But the fallacy can be avoided by limiting the quantity of the original E proposition in its contra
positive. That is, an E proposition's valid contrapositive is an O proposition in which subject and
predicate have been switched and pre-fixed by 'non.' Thus consider
39 No leopards are reptiles.
The correct contrapositive, one that limits the quantity of (39) while preserving its quality, is
(39'), which is also true.
39' Some non-reptiles are not non-leopards.
(40) is inferred from (39) by contraposition without limitation, which makes the inference invalid.
Cf) w
0
z
w
cc
w
LL
z
w
0
w
2
2
cc
w
I
1--
0
w
�
CHAPTER
Categorical
Syllogisms
Here you’ll read more about traditional logic. This chapter is entirely devoted to
syllogistic arguments. It first explains what categorical syllogisms are and then
examines two methods of checking them for validity. The topics include
Recognizing categorical syllogisms.
How to determine the form of a syllogism on the basis of its mood and figure.
Testing syllogism forms for validity using Venn diagrams.
Distribution of terms.
Testing syllogism forms for validity using traditional logic’s rules of validity.
Some patterns of failed syllogism.
330
14.1 What Is a Categorical Syllogism?
Beginning in antiquity with Aristotelian logic, and continuing for many centuries in other
schools of logic, a number of methods have been proposed for analyzing deductive arguments
of the sort we have broadly called ‘syllogistic.’ A syllogism is a deductive argument with two
premises. A categorical syllogism is a syllogism made up entirely of categorical propositions.
Thus there are several different kinds of syllogistic argument, some of which were considered
in Chapters s and 12. In this chapter, we’ll look closely at categorical syllogisms, which, for our
purposes here, we’ll refer to simply as ‘syllogisms.’ For example,
1 1. All rectangles are polygons.
2. All squares are rectangles.
3. All squares are polygons.
Argument (1) is a syllogism, since it has two premises and a conclusion, all of which are cate
gorical propositions. A closer look at (1)’s premises and conclusion reveals that it has exactly
three terms in the position of subject or predicate: ‘rectangle,’ ‘polygon,’ and ‘square.’ Each of
these denotes a category (or class) of things, and these categories are related in such a way that
the argument’s conclusion follows validly from its premises. According to that conclusion, the
class of squares is wholly included in the class of polygons, which must be true provided that
(1)’s premises are true. This is a valid deductive argument: its conclusion is entailed by its
premises. But other syllogisms might be invalid. When a syllogism meets the deductive stan
dard of validity, entailment hinges on relations among the terms of three different types that
occur as subject or predicate of the categorical propositions that make up the syllogism. Since
the validity of an argument depends on its having a valid form, several methods have been
proposed for determining when syllogisms have such forms. But before turning to these, more
needs to be said about the structure of standard syllogisms.
The Terms of a Syllogism
A standard syllogism consists of three categorical propositions, two of which function as
premises and one as a conclusion. Each of these has a subject term and a predicate term
denoting two classes of things, with the proposition as a whole representing a certain relation
of exclusion or inclusion among the classes denoted by its subject and predicate terms. Our
inspection of each of the categorical propositions making up (1) above showed that its
component propositions feature subject and predicate terms of three different types: namely,
‘polygon,’ ‘square,’ and ‘rectangle.’ In fact, this is something all standard syllogisms have in
common, since they all feature terms of three different types: the so-called major, minor, and
middle terms. The major term is the predicate of the conclusion. The minor term is the
subject of the conclusion, and the middle term is the term that occurs only in the premises.
Consider (1) again,
1 1. All rectangles are polygons.
2. All squares are rectangles.
3. All squares are polygons.
..J
� (f)
Cl)
�
Cl)
CJ
0
.J
.J
>
Cl)
.J
<(
a:
0
CJ
LI.J
I
<(
IED
By looking at the predicate and subject of (1)'s conclusion, we can identify this syllogism's
major and minor terms respectively: 'polygons' (the conclusion's predicate) and 'squares'
(its subject). Notice that each of these terms occurs also in the premises, but that does not bear
on their status as major and minor terms, which is determined solely by their functions as
predicate and subject of the conclusion. But in (1), there is also the term 'rectangles,' which
occurs in the subject and predicate positions in the premises. It is the 'middle term,' so called
because its function is to mediate between the two premises-to connect them, so that they're
both talking about the same thing. In any syllogism, the middle term occurs in both premises
but not in the conclusion. Another thing to notice is this: that although each of the three terms
of argument (1) is a single word, this is not so in all syllogisms-since sometimes phrases can
function as subject and predicate of a categorical proposition.
Let's now identify the major, minor, and middle terms in
2 1. No military officers are pacifists.
2.. All lieutenant colonels are military officers.
3. No lieutenant colonels are pacifists.
By using the rule just suggested, we can determine that the major term here is 'pacifists,' the
minor term 'lieutenant colonels,' and middle term 'military officers.'
BOX 1 ■ A SYLLOGISM'S TERMS
The important thing to keep in mind is that in order to identify the three words or phrases that
are to count as the terms of a syllogism, we look first to the syllogism's conclusion. The major
term is whatever word or phrase turns up in the predicate place (i.e., after the copula) in the
conclusion. The minor term is whatever word or phrase turns up in the subject place
(i.e., between the quantifier and the copula) in the conclusion. And the middle term is the term
that does not occur in the conclusion at all but occurs in both premises-whether it be a single
word, as in (1), or a more complex expression, as in (2.).
The Premises of a Syllogism
The conclusion of (1) above is the proposition
I 3. All squares are polygons.
In the notation of traditional logic, this is symbolized as
3'.AIISareP
It is common practice to represent the minor and major terms of a syllogism as 'S' and 'P'
respectively, and its middle term as 'M.' We'll adopt that practice and represent any syllogism
by replacing its three terms by those symbols, keeping logical words such as quantifiers and
negation. In the case of (1) above, we thus obtain
1 ' 1 All M are P
2 All Sare M
3 All Sare P
In a standard syllogism, the minor and the major terms occur in different premises. That con
taining the major term is the 'major premise.' Since (1)'s major term is 'polygons,' its major
premise is
1 . All rectangles are polygons.
In symbols this becomes
1'. All MareP
The premise that contains the minor term is the minor premise. Since (1)'s minor term is
'squares,' its minor premise is
2. All squares are rectangles.
In symbols this becomes
2'. All Sare M
You may have noticed that, in both examples of syllogism considered thus far, each has been
arranged with its major premise first, its minor premise second, and its conclusion last. This is
standard order for a reconstructed syllogism. Although in ordinary speech and writing a
syllogism's premises and conclusion might be jumbled in any order whatsoever, when we
reconstruct it, its premises must be put into standard order (this will become especially
important later). We can now determine which premise is which in (1) above:
1 ' 1. All M are P
2. All Sare M
3. All Sare P
¢:i MAJOR PREMISE
¢:i MINOR PREMISE
Recognizing Syllogisms
However jumbled they may be in their real-life occurrences, syllogisms can be recognized by
first identifying their conclusions. Once we've identified the conclusion of a putative
syllogism, we can check whether it is indeed a syllogism: the conclusion's predicate gives us
the major term, its subject the minor term. Once we've identified these terms, we can then
look at the argument's premises and ask: Which premise contains the major term? (That's the
major premise.) Which contains the minor term? (That's the minor premise.) After listing
these in the standard order, as premises 1 and 2 respectively, and replacing its relevant terms
_J
-<
0
a:
0
('J
LU
0
-<
� ('•
f- �
< Cl)
I-
3: g
� _J
-–
� w
(/)
:-:2′
(/)
0
0
….I
….I
>
(/)
….I
Minor premise ¢ (Listed second)
When the minor term, major term, and middle term are replaced by ‘S,’ ‘P,’ and ‘M,’ as before,
we find this pattern:
4″ 1. All P are M
2. No Sare M
3. No Sare P
This is one among the many possible patterns of syllogisms. Some such patterns are valid,
others invalid. Before we turn to some methods for determining which is which, let’s have a
closer look at argument patterns of this syllogistic sort.
14.2 Syllogistic Argument Forms
Traditionally, syllogisms are said to have forms, which are determined by their figures and
moods. We’ll consider these one at a time, beginning with figure.
Figure
Since a syllogism has three terms (major, minor, and middle), each of which occurs twice in
either subject or predicate position, there are the four possible “figures” or configurations of
these terms for any such argument:
1st Figure
MP
SM
SP
2nd Figure
PM
SM
SP
3rd Figure
MP
MS
SP
4th Figure
PM
MS
SP
(j)
�
a:
0
LL
1-
z
w
�
::i
<..'.J
a:
<(
0
1-
(j)
<..'.J
0
.....J
.....J
>
(j)
N
st
If)
�
If)
CJ
0
_J
_J
>
If)
_J
(/)
�
st
(j)
�
(j)
G
0
-‘
-‘
>
(j)
-‘
<(
0
a:
0
G
w
0
Let's try the whole process of finding a syllogism's form, starting at the beginning.
Consider this argument:
8 No campus residence halls without wi-fi are good places to live. After all, some
campus residence halls without wi-fi are old buildings, but some old buildings are
not good places to live.
Argument (8)'s conclusion is
No campus residence halls without wi-fi are good places to live.
How do we know? Because we have read the argument carefully and asked ourselves: What
claim is being made? (In addition, the premises are introduced by an indicator, 'after all').
Having found the conclusion, we then look for its predicate and subject, which are the major
and minor terms, respectively:
P = 'good places to live'
S = 'campus residence halls without wi-fi'
We can now identify the syllogism's major and minor premises. Since the major premise must
contain the major term, it must be
Some old buildings are not good places to live.
We can therefore put this as the first premise. Similarly, the minor premise must contain the
minor term, so it must be
Some campus residence halls without wi-fi are old buildings.
That is the second premise. Thus the reconstructed syllogism is
9 1. Some old buildings are not good places to live.
2. Some campus residence halls without wi-fi are old buildings.
3. No campus residence halls without wi-fi are good places to live.
Argument (9) illustrates a pattern that may be represented as
9' 1. Some M are not P
2. Some S are M
3. No Sare P
Any syllogism illustrating this pattern would be of the form OIE-1. For example,
1 0 1. Some CIA operatives are not FBI agents.
2. Some women are CIA operatives.
3. No women are FBI agents.
Now something has gone wrong with (10) and any other syllogism along the same pattern
that of (9') above. Clearly, any such syllogism may have true premises and a false conclusion.
Next we'll consider which syllogistic patterns are valid and which are not.
Exercises
1. What is generally understood by 'syllogism' and 'categorical syllogism'?
2. How do we identify the major term, minor term, and middle term of a syllogism?
3. What is meant by 'major premise'?
4. What is meant by 'minor premise'?
5. When is a syllogism in standard order?
6. How do we identify the mood of a syllogism?
7. How do we identify the figure of a syllogism?
8. How do we determine the form of a syllogism?
II. For each of the following arguments, determine whether it is a syllogism. If it isn't,
indicate why, and move on to the next argument. If it is, put the syllogism into
standard order, and replace its major, minor, and middle terms with the appropriate
symbol 'P,' 'S,' or 'M.'
1. Some dinosaurs are not members of the reptile family. For no members of the reptile family are mammals
and some dinosaurs are mammals.
SAMPLE ANSWER:
1 . No members of the reptile family are mammals.
2 Some dinosaurs are mammals.
3 Some dinosaurs are not members of the reptile family.
1. NoPareM
2. Some Sare M
3. Some S are not P
2. Some Japanese car manufacturers make fuel-efficient cars, but no fuel-efficient cars are pickup
trucks. Since all pickup trucks are expensive vehicles, therefore no Japanese car manufacturers
make expensive vehicles.
*3. All North American rivers are navigable. It follows that no North American rivers are non-navigable.
4. Some summer tourists are mountain climbers. For some risk takers are summer tourists and all
mountain climbers are risk takers.
*5. No Sinatra songs are popular with first graders, since all Sinatra songs are romantic songs and no
romantic songs are popular with first graders.
*6. Some men are Oscar winners but no Oscar winners are talk-show hosts. Thus some men are not
talk-show hosts.
7. Some persons knowledgeable about heart disease are not members of the American Heart Association.
For one thing, although some cardiologists are members of the American Heart Association, some
aren't. In addition, all cardiologists are persons knowledgeable about heart disease.
8. No eye doctors are optometrists but some eye doctors are professionals with MD degrees. It follows
that some professionals with MD degrees are not optometrists.
(f)
�
0::
0
LL
1-
z
w
�
::J
(!)
0::
<(
0
1-
(f)
(!)
0
_J
_J
>
(f)
N
7
(/)
�
(/)
(.!)
0
….J
….J
>
(/)
….J
�
0
a:
0
(.!)
w
0
*9. All metals are substances that expand under heat. Therefore, it is not the case that some metals are
not substances that expand under heat.
10. No conservatives are supporters of gay marriage. Hence, some supporters of gay marriage are persons
who favor abortion rights, since no conservatives are persons who favor abortion rights.
*11. All computer scientists are programmers, and some programmers are pool players. It follows that
some computer scientists are pool players.
12. No movie reviewers are mathematicians. Since all mathematicians are experts in geometry and some
mathematicians are experts in geometry, it follows that no movie reviewers are experts in geometry.
Ill. For each of the following syllogistic forms, identify its mood and figure.
1. 1. Some M are P
2. Some M are S
3. Some S are not P
SAMPLE ANSWER: 110-3
2. 1. No Mare P
2. No Sare M
3. No Sare P
3. 1. Some Pare not M
2. Some S are not M
3. All Sare P
*4. 1. All Mare P
2. Some S are M
3.AII Sare P
5. 1. Some Pare M
2. Some S are M
3. Some S are P
*6. 1. No P are M
2.AIIMareS
3.AII Sare P
7. 1. Some Mare P
2.AIIMareS
3. No Sare P
*8. 1. Some Mare not P
2. Some S are not M
3. NoS are P
9. 1. Some Pare M
2. All Sare M
3. All Sare P
*10. 1. Some Mare not P
2. Some S are M
3. Some S are P
11. 1. Some P are not M
2. Some M are not S
3. Some S are P
•12. 1. No Mare P
2. No Mare S
3. All Sare P
IV. Reconstruct each of the following syllogisms and give its form:
1. Since all Italian sports cars are fast cars, it follows that no fast cars are inexpensive machines,
because no inexpensive machines are Italian sports cars.
SAMPLE ANSWER: EAE-4
1 . No inexpensive machines are Italian sports cars.
2. All Italian sports cars are fast cars.
3. No fast cars are inexpensive machines.
1. NoPareM
2. AIIMareS
3. NoS are P
2. Because no airlines that fly to Uzbekistan are airlines that offer discount fares, some airlines that offer
discount fares are carriers that are not known for their safety records. For some carriers that are not
known for their safety records are airlines that fly to Uzbekistan.
*3. Since some residents of California are people who are not Lawrence Welk fans, and all people who
listen to reggae music are people who are not Lawrence Welk fans, we may infer that some residents
of California are people who listen to reggae music.
4. No members of the Committee for Freedom are people who admire dictators. For all members of
the Committee for Freedom are libertarians, and no libertarians are people who admire dictators.
*5. All loyal Americans are people who are willing taxpayers. Hence, all people who are willing taxpayers
are supporters of the president in his desire to trim the federal budget, for all loyal Americans are sup
porters of the president in his desire to trim the federal budget.
6. All Rottweilers that are easily annoyed are animals that are avoided by letter carriers; for some lap dogs
are not Rottweilers that are easily annoyed, but no animals that are avoided by letter carriers are lap dogs.
*7. No reptiles weighing over eighty pounds are animals that are convenient house pets. After all, all
animals that are convenient house pets are creatures your Aunt Sophie would like, but no creatures
your Aunt Sophie would like are reptiles weighing over eighty pounds.
8. Since some senators are people who will not take bribes, and all people who will not take bribes are
honest people, it follows that some senators are honest people.
*9. No explosives are safe things to carry in the trunk of your car. For some explosives are devices that
contain dynamite, and some devices that contain dynamite are not safe things to carry in the trunk of
your car.
10. No chiropractors are surgeons. Hence, some chiropractors are not persons who are licensed to perform
a coronary bypass, since some persons who are licensed to perform a coronary bypass are surgeons.
•11. No pacifists are persons who favor the use of military force. Hence, some persons who favor the use
of military force are not conscientious objectors, for some pacifists are not conscientious objectors.
12. Some rhinos are not dangerous animals, because all dangerous animals are creatures that are kept
in zoos, and some rhinos are not creatures that are kept in zoos.
(/)
�
rr
0
LL
1-
z
UJ
�
🙂
(9
rr
(/)
EDI
(j)
�
(j)
Cl
0
_J
_J
>
(j)
_J
<(
0
a:
0
Cl
w
I
<(
V. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1 . For each of the following syllogistic forms, provide a syllogism that is an instance of it:
1 AAA-1
2 AEE-2
3 OAO-3
4 EIO-4
5 All-3
6 EAE-1
7 EAE-2
8 AEE-4
9 IAl-3
10 IAl-4
2. All of the above syllogistic forms are valid. What do you now know about the conclusion of a syllogism
that exemplifies any of them? And what would you know about any such syllogism if its premises were
in fact true?
14.3 Testing for Validity with Venn Diagrams
Syllogisms can have configurations that make up 256 different forms. Since some of these are
valid and some are not, it is essential that there be some dependable way of determining, for
any given syllogistic form, whether it is valid. In fact, there are several different ways of doing
this, but we shall focus here on one very widely accepted technique, based on Venn diagrams,
the rudiments of which we examined in Chapter 13.
How to Diagram a Standard Syllogism
In using Venn diagrams to check the validity of syllogisms, we adapt that system of two
circle diagrams for categorical propositions to a larger diagram with three interlocking
circles.
M
Figure 1
Here the circles represent the three distinct classes of things denoted by the three terms of a
syllogism. The two bottom circles, labeled S and P, represent the classes denoted by the syllo
gism's minor and major terms.
BOX 5 ■ VALIDITY AND VENN DIAGRAMS
Any syllogism could be tested for validity by means of a Venn diagram, which would begin with
three intersecting circles as in Figure 1. Once the Venn diagram is completed, it shows whether
the syllogism is valid or invalid.
The top circle, labeled 'M,' represents the class denoted by the syllogism's middle term. Now
notice another thing about this diagram: we can find within it subclass spaces of two
important shapes that will be crucial to our diagrams. We've already encountered these in the
two-circle diagrams discussed in the last chapter. They are the American football shape (Figure 2)
and the crescent (Figure 3):
0
Figure 2 Figure 3
On the three-circle Venn diagram, the football shape can be found in three places. Can you see
where? The crescent can be found in six places. Can you locate these? For the purpose of
putting shading or xs on the three-circle Venn diagram, the only subclass spaces we'll be con
cerned with are those in the shape of either a football or a crescent. If you try to shade or put
an x in any other shape, you'll not be using the Venn system.
Finally, notice that on the three-circle diagram, there are three different ways of grouping
the circles together into pairs.
CONCLUSION
Figure 4
z
z
w
>
I
1–
>-1–
0
_J
<( >
0:
0 u..
(!j
z
i= (/)
(/)� w <(
1-- 0:
(') (!j
.,i �
�o
mlll
(j)
�
(j)
CJ
0
_J
_J
>
(j)
_J
<(
0
a:
0
CJ
w
11111
These three groupings mark the areas where each of a syllogism's three propositions are
represented: Mand Pare used to diagram its major premise, Mand Sits minor premise, and
Sand Pits conclusion. Again, the purpose of drawing this sort of three-circle Venn diagram is
to test the validity of a syllogism. But the test requires that we diagram propositions across
two circles at a time, using what we have learned in Chapter 13 about Venn diagrams for each
of the four types of categorical proposition. To do this, we take into account, one at a time,
pairs of circles representing the major premise, minor premise, and the conclusion, in each
case ignoring the circle that is irrelevant to the task at hand. To see how this works, let's test
a syllogism.
11 1. No poets are cynics.
2. All police detectives are poets.
3. No police detectives are cynics.
A quick look reveals that this syllogism is already in standard order, so the first step in argu
ment analysis has been done. We can then see that the major term is 'cynics,' the minor term
'police detectives,' and the middle term 'poets' -so that the argument is an instance of the
form EAE-1, which we could spell out in this standard way:
11 1
1. NoMareP
2. All Sare M
3. No Sare P
Now, are syllogisms of this form valid or invalid? A Venn diagram can test this. The first rule to
follow in implementing this test is:
Diagram only the syllogism's premises. Do not try to diagram the conclusion.
So we are concerned at this stage only with two sets of two circles each. One set will be used to
represent the major premise (Figure s), the other to represent the minor premise (Figure 6):
M M
Figure 5 Figure 6
Now, which premise shall we diagram first? Here the rule, whose rationale will soon become
apparent, is
If one premise is universal and the other particular, you must diagram the universal
premise first, whichever it is. But if both premises are universal, or both particular, it
doesn't matter which is diagrammed first.
In (n')'s case, both premises are universal, so it's a matter of indifference which one we choose
to diagram first. Let's arbitrarily choose the major premise, an E proposition of the form 'No S
are P' that we earlier learned to diagram this way:
No Sare P
Figure 7
When drawn directly on the pair of circles in the larger diagram, the diagram looks like this:
M
No Mare P
Figure 8
So much for the major premise. Now what about the minor? In (111 ) the minor premise is an A
proposition, and the two-circle Venn diagram that represents it, you'll recall, is
All Sare P
Figure 9
z
z
llJ
>
I
f-
>
f-
0
…J
<{
>
a:
0
0
z
;::: Cf)
Cf)�
llJ <{
f- a:
C') 0
. <{
Cf)
_J
I
f-
>
f-
0
….J
<( >
a:
0
LJ…
CJ
z
;:: (/)
(/) � w <(
f- a:
(')0
��
�o
Cf)
�
Cf)
(')
0
..J
..J
>
(/J
..J
I
f-
>
f-
…J
a:
0
LJ..
CJ
z
i= (/)
(/)�
LU
(f)
_.J
<{ � a: 0 CJ LU - When we represent that premise in the three-circle diagram, we get this: M Figure 18 Why? Because in Figure 18, the crescent-shaped space where the 'x' goes in representing "Some M are not P" is itself divided by a line, and on neither side of it do we find shading. Had one or the other of these two portions of the crescent been shaded out, the 'x' would have gone in the other part. But here, there's no shading at all inside the crescent; therefore, if we are to put an 'x' inside it, we have no choice but to put the 'x' on the line dividing the crescent-to indicate that we're non-committal about precisely which side of the line it goes on. Given that the crescent, "M that are non-P," is divided by a line, it is simply not decidable on which side of it the 'x' goes. Now we're finished with the diagramming and ready to check for validity. We compare the conclusion of the argument with the part of the diagram that represents it. Do they match up? Clearly, in this case they do not. For the conclusion of the argument is the E proposition 'No S are P.' A correct Venn diagram for any such proposition shows the inter section between S and P shaded out (see Figure 7 above). But that is not what Figure 18 represents. So here's an instance where the process of diagramming the premises did not automatically produce in the bottom pair of circles a diagram that represents the conclusion as given. Thus the Venn diagram proves the form OIE-1 to be invalid. We conclude that argument (9) is invalid. BOX 7 ■ SECTION SUMMARY How to test the validity of a syllogism with a Venn diagram: ■ Draw three intersecting circles. ■ Diagram only the premises. ■ If one premise is universal and the other particular, you must diagram the universal premise first, whichever it is. ■ But if both premises are universal or both particular, then it doesn't matter which is diagrammed first. ■ Once you have diagrammed the premises, if the conclusion is already unequivocally diagrammed too, the argument is valid. Otherwise, the argument is invalid. Exercises 1. In using a Venn diagram to represent an argument form, what are the only two shapes in which shading or an 'x' can go? 2. In a three-circle Venn diagram, what is represented by each of the circles? 3. Which part of a Venn diagram represents the major premise of a syllogism? 4. Which part of a Venn diagram represents the minor premise of a syllogism? 5. In diagramming a syllogism with a Venn diagram, which premise is diagrammed first? 6. How do we tell, using a Venn diagram, whether a syllogism is valid or not? VII. Reconstruct each of the following syllogisms, identify its form, and test it for validity with a Venn diagram. 1. Since all logicians are philosophers, and some philosophers are not vegetarians, it follows that some logicians are not vegetarians. SAMPLE ANSWER: 1 Some philosophers are not vegetarians. 2 All logicians are philosophers. 3 Some logicians are not vegetarians. I. Some Jf are not P. 2. All Sare _\1, 3. Some .5' are not P. OAO-I INVALID 2. No dictators are humanitarians, because no tyrants are humanitarians, and some dictators are tyrants. 3. Some medical conditions that are not treatable by conventional means are causes of death. Hence, some causes of death are not things related to eating pizza, for no medical conditions that are not treatable by conventional means are things related to eating pizza. *4. Some taxi drivers are people who never run red lights, because all taxi drivers are people who are not elitists, and some people who never run red lights are people who are not elitists. 5. Some economists who are members of the faculty at the University of Chicago are not monetarists; therefore, no monetarists are White Sox fans, for all economists who are members of the faculty at the University of Chicago are White Sox fans. 6. Since all readers of poetry are benevolent people, it follows that no fanatics are benevolent people, for no fanatics are readers of poetry. *7. No armadillos are intelligent creatures, for all intelligent creatures are things that will stay out of the middle of the highway, but no armadillos are things that will stay out of the middle of the highway. 8. No newspaper columnists are motorcycle racers; however, some motorcycle racers are attorneys. Therefore, some attorneys are not newspaper columnists. z z w >
I
1-
3
>-
1-
0
_J
((
0
u..
(‘.J
z
� (/)
(/) �
w
(f)
_J
<(
0
a:
0
CJ
w
111m
9. Some candidates for public office are not persons who are well known. After all, some citizens who
are listed on the ballot are not persons who are well known, and all citizens who are listed on the
ballot are candidates for public office.
*10. Because some axolotls are creatures that are not often seen in the city, we may infer that some mud
lizards that are found in the jungles of southern Mexico are creatures that are not often seen in the
city, since all axolotls are mud lizards that are found in the jungles of southern Mexico.
11. Since some members of Congress are not senators, it follows that some members of Congress are
not experienced politicians, for all senators are experienced politicians.
12. Some historical developments are not entirely explainable. After all, all historical developments are
contingent things, and no contingent things are entirely explainable.
*13. All orthodontists are dentists who have done extensive post-doctoral study, but no impoverished
persons are dentists who have done extensive post-doctoral study. Thus no orthodontists are
impoverished persons.
14. All people who ride bicycles in rush-hour traffic are courageous people, for some courageous people
are professors who are not tenured members of the faculty, and no professors who are not tenured
members of the faculty are people who ride bicycles in rush-hour traffic.
15. Some investment brokers are not Harvard graduates. So some financiers are not investment
brokers, since some financiers are not Harvard graduates.
*16. All philosophy majors are rational beings, but no parakeets are rational beings. Therefore, no
parakeets are philosophy majors.
17. Since some wars are inevitable occurrences, and no inevitable occurrences are things that can be
prevented, it follows that some wars are not things that can be prevented.
18. All factory workers are union members, for some union members are not persons who are easy to
convince, and some factory workers are not persons who are easy to convince.
*19. Since no hallucinations are optical illusions, we may infer that some misunderstandings that are not
avoidable are optical illusions, for some misunderstandings that are not avoidable are hallucinations.
20. Some senators who are not opponents of foreign aid are friends of the president. But all friends of
the president are influential people who are well informed about world events; hence, some senators
who are not opponents of foreign aid are influential people who are well informed about world events.
21. Some fantastic creatures that are not found anywhere in nature are not dogfish. So we may infer that
no dogfish are fish that bark, since some fantastic creatures that are not found anywhere in nature
are fish that bark.
*22. Some college presidents are not benevolent despots, for no benevolent despots are defenders of
faculty autonomy, and no defenders of faculty autonomy are college presidents.
23. Since some elderly professors who are not bald are respected scholars, it follows that some classi
cal philologists are respected scholars. For no elderly professors who are not bald are classical
philologists.
24. Some people who have quit smoking are people who are not enthusiastic sports fans, but no soccer
players are people who are not enthusiastic sports fans. So some people who have quit smoking are
soccer players.
*25. All philanderers are habitual prevaricators. Therefore, no preachers who are well-known television
personalities are philanderers, because no habitual prevaricators are preachers who are well-known
television personalities.
26. Some pinchpennies are not alumni who are immensely wealthy. For no pinchpennies are generous
contributors to their alma mater, and some alumni who are immensely wealthy are generous contrib
utors to their alma mater.
27. All persons employed by the state government are civil servants, for no persons employed by the
state government are persons who are eligible to participate in the state lottery, and no civil servants
are persons who are eligible to participate in the state lottery.
*28. Since all great music is uplifting, it follows that some jazz is great music, for some jazz is uplifting.
29. No Muscovites are country bumpkins, but some Russians who are veterans of World War II are not
Muscovites. Hence, some country bumpkins are not Russians who are veterans of World War II.
*30. Some interest-bearing bank accounts are not an effective means of increasing one's wealth. After
all, some investments that are insured by the federal government are not an effective means of
increasing one's wealth, and all investments that are insured by the federal government are interest
bearing bank accounts.
VIII. YOUR OWN THINKING LAB
1. It is sometimes said that the conclusion of a valid syllogism is already contained in its premises. How
could this be explained in connection with Venn diagrams for testing the validity of syllogisms?
2. For each form represented below, give two syllogisms of your own:
M M
M M
z
z
w
>
I
l-
s:
>
‘:::
0
…..J
cc
0
C)
z
i= (j’J
(j’J �
w
if)
…J
<(
(.)
a:
0
(')
w
MHI
14.4 Distribution of Terms
Although Venn Diagrams provide a reliable way of checking syllogistic forms for validity, they
are not the only way of doing so. Another method relies on a short list of rules of validity that
any indisputably valid syllogism must follow and a list of fallacies that any such syllogism nec
essarily avoids. We'll devote the remainder of this chapter to a look at some details of this tech
nique, which is based on one of the traditional parts of Aristotelian logic, To use this method,
it's first necessary to understand the notion of distribution of terms.
Earlier, we saw that one use of the word 'term' is to refer to the substantive parts of a cat
egorical proposition: its subject and predicate are its terms. To describe a term as 'distributed'
is to say that it's referring to an entire class. In a proposition that is universal affirmative, the
pattern of distribution is:
A proposition= subject distributed, predicate undistributed
Thus in
13 All oranges are citrus fruits,
the subject term, 'oranges,' is distributed, since, preceded by 'all,' it's plainly referring to the
whole class of oranges. But its predicate term, 'citrus fruits,' is not distributed, since no univer
sal claim of any kind is being made here about all members of the class of things to which it
refers-namely, citrus fruits.
In a proposition that is universal negative, the pattern of distribution is
E proposition: subject distributed, predicate distributed.
Consider
14 No apples are citrus fruits,
which is true, and, as we saw in Chapter 13, logically equivalent to
14' No citrus fruits are apples.
Either way, these propositions deny of the whole class of apples that it includes citrus fruits,
and of the whole class of citrus fruits that it includes apples. Put a different way, (14) is asserting
that there is total, mutual exclusion between the whole classes of apples and citrus fruits. So it's
clear that in (14) both the subject term and the predicate term are distributed. Here something
is being said about entire classes (namely, that they exclude each other).
Let's now turn to the patterns of distribution for particular propositions, which include
particular affirmatives such as
15 Some oranges are edible fruits,
and particular negatives, such as
16 Some oranges are not edible fruits.
The pattern of distribution for any particular affirmative proposition is
/ proposition: subject undistributed, predicate undistributed
and for any particular negative proposition it is
0 proposition: subject undistributed, predicate distributed
(15) amounts to the proposition that there is at least one orange that is an edible fruit. This
proposition's subject is undistributed because this term doesn't refer to the whole class of
oranges, but only to 'some' of them. Similarly, its predicate term, 'edible fruits,' is equally
undistributed, since this term doesn't refer to the whole class of edible fruits but only to those
edible fruits that are oranges.
Finally, although the subject of (16) is not distributed for the reasons just provided for the
subject of (15), its predicate term is. Why? Because it refers to the class of edible fruits as a
whole, which becomes plain when (16) is recast as the proposition that there is at least one
orange that is not in the class (taken as a whole) of edible fruits. (16) says that the entire class of
edible fruits excludes at least one orange
To sum up, the four patterns of distribution are as follows:
A (universal affirmative)
E (universal negative)
I (particular affirmative)
0 (particular negative)
All Sare P
No Sare P
Some Sare P
Some S are not P
Subject distributed, predicate not
Both terms distributed
Neither term distributed
Predicate distributed, subject not
Keeping in mind the pattern of distribution outlined here (and also below) will make it easier
for you to use the rules of validity to determine whether syllogistic argument forms are valid or
invalid.
A and E: universal, subject distributed
E and 0: negative, predicate distributed
SUBJECT
A DISTRIBUTED E
-------,
l PREDICATE
I DISTRIBUTED
0
CJ)
2
er:
w
1-
u..
0
z
0
1-
::J
co
I
C/)
0
s:i:
'Sj"
U)
L
U)
(')
0
...J
...J
>
U)
…J
<(
0
a:
0
(')
w
0
-
14.5 Rules of Validity and Syllogistic Fallacies
Here we'll consider six rules that can be put at the service of testing the validity of any given
categorical syllogism.
BOX 8 ■ DETERMINING VALIDITY WITH THE SIX RULES
■ Any syllogism that obeys all six rules is valid.
■ Any syllogism that breaks even one rule is invalid-though some syllogisms may break more
than one .
We'll also look at the fallacies that are committed when these rules are broken. First proposed
in Aristotelian logic, rules along the lines we'll discuss here represent an alternative to Venn
diagrams as a procedure for determining the validity of syllogisms. Let's consider each of
these rules one at a time, together with its rationale.
RULE 1: A syllogism must have exactly three terms.
The conclusion of a syllogism is a categorical proposition where two terms are related in a
certain way. But they could be so related only if there is a third term to which the subject and
predicate of the conclusion are each independently related. That is, for a syllogism's con
clusion to follow validly from its two premises, there must be precisely three terms, no more
and no fewer, each occurring twice: the major term as the predicate of the conclusion and as
either the subject or predicate of the major premise; the minor term as the subject of the con
clusion and as either the subject or predicate of the minor premise; and the middle term once
in each of the premises, where it may appear as either subject or predicate.
Syllogisms sometimes flout this rule of validity by having some term used with two
different meanings in its two occurrences, so that the argument equivocates (see Chapter 9).
Any such argument is said to commit the fallacy of four terms (or Q_uaternio Terminorum). For
example, consider
17 1. All the members of that committee are snakes.
2. All snakes are reptiles.
3. All members of that committee are reptiles.
Here the term 'snakes' is plainly used with two different meanings. As a result, the syllogism
commits the fallacy of four terms and is therefore invalid.
RULE 2: The middle term must be distributed at least once.
A syllogism's middle term, you'll recall, is the term that occurs in both premises (and only in
the premises). It functions to connect the minor and major terms, so that the relation among
these could be as presented in the syllogism's conclusion. But the middle term can do that only
if it's referring to a whole class in at least one of the premises, for if it refers to one class or part
of a class in the major premise and another in the minor, then the minor and major terms
would be connected to things that have nothing in common. As a result, the relation among
these terms would not be as presented in the syllogism's conclusion. Any such syllogism com
mits the fallacy of undistributed middle and is invalid-as, for example, is this argument:
18 1. All feral pigeons are birds with feathers.
2. Some birds with feathers are animals that distract attackers.
3. Some animals that distract attackers are feral pigeons.
RULE 3: If any term is distributed in the conclusion, it must be distributed also in the
premise in which it occurs.
Recall that the mark of validity for an argument is that its conclusion must follow necessarily
from its premises. But no argument can be valid in that sense if its conclusion says more than
what is already said in the premises. Syllogisms, which are deductive arguments, fail to be valid
when their conclusions go beyond what is supported by their premises. That is the case of a
syllogism whose minor or major term is distributed in the conclusion (thus referring there to
a whole class) but not in the premise in which it also occurs (referring there to only part of a
class). Any such syllogism commits the fallacy of illicit process, which may involve either the
minor or major term. Thus the fallacy has the following two versions:
OFTIIE The major term is distributed in the conclusion �
MAJORTERM
,___
but not in the major premise.
IWCIT
PROCESS -
OFTIIE The minor term is distributed in the conclusion
MINORTERM
,___
but not in the minor premise.
Consider
1 9 1. All tigers are felines.
2. No lions are tigers.
3. No lions are felines.
The term 'felines' in (19)'s conclusion involves the whole class of felines, which is said to be
excluded from the whole class of lions. But premise 1 is not about the whole class of felines,
since there the term 'felines' is not distributed. The fallacy committed by this argument is illicit
process of the major term (for short, 'illicit major').
Now consider
20 1. All suicide bombers are persons willing to die.
2. All suicide bombers are opponents of the status quo.
3. All opponents of the status quo are persons willing to die.
0
I
(/)
(')
0
_J
_J
>
(/)
0
z
<
>
I-
0
_J
;;;
LL
0
(/)
w (/)
_J w
:::> –
a: �
“: :::J
<:!"
(J)
_J
<(
0
a:
0
CJ
LU
0
MM:i
The term 'opponents of the status quo' in (20)'s conclusion involves a whole class of people
with a certain view, which is said to be included in the class denoted by the major term. But
premise 2 is not about that whole class of people, since there the term 'opponents of the status
quo' is the predicate of an A proposition and therefore not distributed. The fallacy committed
by this argument is illicit process of the minor term (for short, ' illicit minor').
Finally, notice that it is also possible for an argument to commit both of these fallacies at
once. One more thing: since there's no distribution in a type-I proposition, any syllogism with
a type-I conclusion obeys rule 3 by default. But if the conclusion is an A, E, or O proposition,
then it'll have some distributed term in it, and the logical thinker will want to make sure that
any term distributed in the conclusion is also distributed in the appropriate premise.
RULE 4: A valid syllogism cannot have two negative premises.
If a syllogism's major premise is negative, the classes denoted by its middle and major terms
either wholly or partially exclude each other. And if its minor premise is also negative, the
classes denoted by its middle and minor term also either wholly or partially exclude each
other. From such premises no conclusion validly follows about the relation between the
classes denoted by the minor and major terms. When this happens, the argument is said to
commit the fallacy of exclusive premises-for example,
21 1. No ferns are trees.
2. Some elms are not ferns.
3. Some elms are not trees.
The upshot of rule 4 is that certain combinations in the premises will always render a syllo
gism invalid: EE, EO, OE, and 00. To avoid this fallacy, if one of the syllogism's premises is
negative, the other must be affirmative.
RULE 5: If there is a negative premise, the conclusion must be negative; and if there
is a negative conclusion, there must be one negative premise.
Recall that affirmative categorical propositions represent class inclusion, either whole inclu
sion of one class in another (A proposition), or inclusion of part of a class within another class
(I proposition). Thus the class inclusion represented in a syllogism's affirmative conclusion
could be validly inferred only when both premises also represent class inclusion. On the other
hand, a syllogism's negative conclusion, which would represent a relation of class exclusion,
cannot follow validly from two affirmative premises (which assert only relations of inclusion).
When rule 5 is violated, a syllogism commits either the fallacy of drawing an affirmative
conclusion from a negative premise, or that of drawing a negative conclusion from two affirmative
premises. Either way, the syllogism is invalid. For example,
22 1. All humans are mammals.
2. Some lizards are not humans.
3. Some lizards are mammals.
This commits the fallacy of drawing an affinnative conclusion.from a negative premise; while
23 1. All poets are creative writers.
2. All creative writers are authors.
3. No authors are poets.
commits the fallacy of drawing a negative conclusion .from two affirmative premises. Syllogisms
flouting rule 5 are so obviously invalid that it is rare to encounter them. Finally, note that any
syllogism containing only affirmative propositions obeys rule s by default.
RULE 6: If both premises are universal, the conclusion must be universal.
As we saw in the previous chapter, of the four types of standard categorical propositions, only
I and O carry existential import; that is, only these presuppose the existence of the entities
denoted by their subject terms. Thus there is no valid syllogism with two universal premises
and a particular conclusion. Any such syllogism draws a conclusion with existential import on
the basis of premises having no such import. Syllogisms of this sort violate rule 6, committing
the so-called existential fallacy. For example,
24 1. All beings that breathe are mortal.
2. All mermaids are beings that breathe.
3. Some mermaids are mortal.
Here the conclusion is equivalent to "There is at least one mermaid that is mortal"-in effect
endorsing the existence of mermaids. Finally, note that any syllogism in which one or more of
its premises is particular (i.e., type I or 0) obeys rule 6 by default.
Rules of Validity vs. Venn Diagrams
Each of the six rules of validity stipulates a necessary condition of validity in categorical syllo
gisms. Thus a syllogism that obeys any one of these rules meets a necessary condition of being
valid. But that is of course not yet to meet a sufficient condition of validity. Only obeying all six
rules together is a sufficient condition for the validity of a syllogism. This technique thus
provides a method of checking for validity that is every bit as reliable as that of Venn diagrams.
The rules could, then, be used together with the Venn diagrams, so that if we make a mistake
in one method, the other method may catch it. Any syllogistic form that commits one or more
of the above fallacies will show up as invalid on a Venn diagram, and any time the diagram
shows a form to be invalid, it will be found to commit one or more fallacies. Likewise, any
syllogistic form that obeys all six rules will be shown valid by a Venn diagram.
In order to use the method of rules and fallacies to check syllogism forms for validity,
you'll want to do two things: (1) keep clearly in mind which rules and fallacies go together, and
(2) remember that the rules and fallacies are not two different ways of saying the same thing!
The rules are prescriptions about what should be kept in mind in assessing the validity of a
syllogism. The fallacies are errors in the reasoning underlying those syllogisms that break the
rules. Each fallacy can be associated with the flouting of one of the rules.
0
1-
(/)
(')
0
_J
_J
>
(/)
0
z
<(
>–
1-
0
_J
<(
>
LL
0
(/)
w (/)
_J w
::> –
a: :i
�j
s:t <(
� LL
Cf)
�
Cf)
('J
0
...J
...J
>
Cf)
…J
<(
0
a:
0
('J
llJ
111m
Again, the six rules collectively stipulate the necessary and sufficient conditions of validity
for categorical syllogisms, but committing even one of the fallacies makes a syllogism invalid.
Since it's valid syllogisms that preserve truth, the rules are to be obeyed and the fallacies to be
avoided.
Let's now summarize the eight fallacies and the six rules of validity that they violate.
Fallacy
Four terms
Undistributed middle
Illicit process of the
major/minor term
Exclusive premises
Affirmative from a negative
and Negative.from two
affirmatives
Existential fallacy
Exercises
1
2
3
4
5
6
Rule Violated
A syllogism must have exactly three terms.
The middle term must be distributed at least once.
If any term is distributed in the conclusion, it must
also be distributed in one of the premises.
A valid syllogism cannot have two negative premises.
If there is a negative premise, the conclusion must be
negative; and if ther